Uncommon Descent Serving The Intelligent Design Community

Defending Intelligent Design theory: Why targets are real targets, probabilities real probabilities, and the Texas Sharp Shooter fallacy does not apply at all.

Share
Facebook
Twitter
LinkedIn
Flipboard
Print
Email

 

 

 

The aim of this OP is to discuss in some order and with some completeness a few related objections to ID theory which are in a way connected to the argument that goes under the name of Texas Sharp Shooter Fallacy, sometimes used as a criticism of ID.

The argument that the TSS fallacy is a valid objection against ID has been many times presented by DNA_Jock, a very good discussant from the other side. So, I will refer in some detail to his arguments, as I understand them and remember them. Of course, if DNA_Jock thinks that I am misrepresenting his ideas, I am ready to ackowledge any correction about that. He can post here, if he can or likes, or at TSZ, where he is a contributor.

However, I thik that the issues discussed in this OP are of general interest, and that they touch some fundamental aspects of the debate.

As an help to those who read this, I will sum up the general structure of this OP, which will probably be rather long. I will discuss three different arguments, somewhat related. They are:

a) The application of the Texas Sharp Shooter fallacy to ID, and why that application is completely wrong.

b) The objection of the different possible levels of function definition.

c) The objection of the possible alternative solutions, and of the incomplete exploration of the search space.

Of course, the issue debated here is, as usual, the design inference, and in particular its application to biological objects.

So, let’s go.

a) The Texas Sharp Shooter fallacy and its wrong application to ID.

 

What’s the Texas Sharp Shooter fallacy (TSS)?

It is a logical fallacy. I quote here a brief description of the basic metaphor, from RationalWiki:

The fallacy’s name comes from a parable in which a Texan fires his gun at the side of a barn, paints a bullseye around the bullet hole, and claims to be a sharpshooter. Though the shot may have been totally random, he makes it appear as though he has performed a highly non-random act. In normal target practice, the bullseye defines a region of significance, and there’s a low probability of hitting it by firing in a random direction. However, when the region of significance is determined after the event has occurred, any outcome at all can be made to appear spectacularly improbable.

For our purposes, we will use a scenario where specific targets are apparently shot by a shooter. This is the scenario that best resembles what we see in biological objects, where we can observe a great number of functional structures, in particular proteins, and we try to understand the causes of their origin.

In ID, as well known, we use functional information as a measure of the improbability of an outcome.  The general idea is similar to Paley’s argument for a watch: a very high level of specific functional information in an object is a very reliable marker of design.

But to evaluate functional information in any object, we must first define a function, because the measure of functional information depends on the function defined. And the observer must be free to define any possible function, and then measure the linked functional information. Respecting these premises, the idea is that if we observe any object that exhibits complex functional information (for example, more than 500 bits of functional information ) for an explicitly defined function (whatever it is) we can safely infer design.

Now, the objection that we are discussing here is that, according to some people (for example DNA_Jock), by defining the function after we have observed the object as we do in ID theory we are committing the TSS fallacy. I will show why that is not the case using an example, because examples are clearer than abstract words.

So, in our example, we have a shooter, a wall which is the target of the shooting, and the shootin itself. And we are the observers.

We know nothing of the shooter. But we know that a shooting takes place.

Our problem is:

  1. Is the shooting a random shooting? This is the null hypothesis

or:

  1. Is the shooter aiming at something? This is the “aiming” hypothesis

So, here I will use “aiming” instead of design, because my neo-darwinist readers will probably stay more relaxed. But, of course, aiming is a form of design (a conscious representation outputted to a material system).

Now I will describe three different scenarios, and I will deal in detail with the third.

  1. First scenario: no fallacy.

In this case, we can look at the wall before the shooting. We see that there are 100 targets painted in different parts of the wall, rather randomly, with their beautiful colors (let’s say red and white). By the way, the wall is very big, so the targets are really a small part of the whole wall, even if taken together.

Then, we witness the shootin: 100 shots.

We go again to the wall, and we find that all 100 shots have hit the targets, one per target, and just at the center.

Without any worries, we infer aiming.

I will not compute the probabilities here, because we are not really interested in this scenario.

This is a good example of pre-definition of the function (the targets to be hit). I believe that neither DNA_Jock nor any other discussant will have problems here. This is not a TSS fallacy.

  1. Second scenario: the fallacy.

The same setting as above. However, we cannot look at the wall before the shooting. No pre-specification.

After the shooting, we go to the wall and paint a target around each of the different shots, for a total of 100. Then we infer aiming.

Of course, this is exactly the TSS fallacy.

There is a post-hoc definition of the function. Moreover, the function is obviously built (painted) to correspond to the information in the shots (their location). More on this later.

Again, I will not deal in detail with this scenario because I suppose that we all agree: this is an example of TSS fallacy, and the aiming inference is wrong.

  1. Third scenario: no fallacy.

The same setting as above. Again, we cannot look at the wall before the shooting. No pre-specification.

After the shooting, we go to the wall. This time, however, we don’t paint anything.

But we observe that the wall is made of bricks, small bricks. Almost all the bricks are brown. But there are a few that are green. Just a few. And they are randomly distributed in the wall.

 

 

We also observe that all the 100 shots have hit green bricks. No brown brick has been hit.

Then we infer aiming.

Of course, the inference is correct. No TSS fallacy here.

And yet, we are using a post-hoc definition of function: shooting the green bricks.

What’s the difference with the second scenario?

The difference is that the existence of the green bricks is not something we “paint”: it is an objective property of the wall. And, even if we do use something that we observe post-hoc (the fact that only the green bricks have been shot) to recognize the function post-hoc, we are not using in any way the information about the specific location of each shot to define the function. The function is defined objectively and independently from the contingent information about the shots.

IOWs, we are not saying: well the shooter was probably aiming at poin x1 (coordinates of the first shot) and point x2 (coordinates of the second shot), and so on. We just recognize that the shooter was aimin at the green bricks.  An objective property of the wall.

IOWs ( I use many IOWs, because I know that this simple concept will meet a great resistance in the minds of our neo-darwinist friends) we are not “painting” the function, we are simply “recognizing” it, and using that recognition to define it.

Well, this third scenario is a good model of the design inference in ID. It corresponds very well to what we do in ID when we make a design inference for functional proteins. Therefore, the procedure we use in ID is no TSS fallacy. Not at all.

Given the importance of this model for our discussion, I will try to make it more quantitative.

Let’s say that the wall is made of 10,000 bricks in total.

Let’s say that there are only 100 green bricks, randomly distributed in the wall.

Let’s say that all the green bricks have been hit, and no brown brick.

What are the probabilities of that result if the null hypothesis is true (IOWs, if the shooter was not aiming at anything) ?

The probability of one succesful hit (where success means hitting a green brick) is of course 0.01 (100/10000).

The probability of having 100 successes in 100 shots can be computed using the binomial distribution. It is:

10e-200

IOWs, the system exhibits 664 bits of functional information. More ore less like the TRIM62 protein, an E3 ligase discussed in my previous OP about the Ubiquitin system, which exhibits an increase of 681 bits of human conserved functional information at the transition to vertebrates.

Now, let’s stop for a moment for a very important step. I am asking all neo-darwinists who are reading this OP a very simple question:

In the above situation, do you infer aiming?

It’s very important, so I will ask it a second time, a little louder:

In the above situation, do you infer aiming? 

Because if your answer is no, if you still think that the above scenario is a case of TSS fallacy, if you still believe that the observed result is not unlikely, that it is perfectly reasonable under the assumption of a random shooting, then you can stop here: you can stop reading this OP, you can stop discussing ID, at least with me. I will go on with the discussion with the reasonable people who are left.

So, in the end of this section, let’s remind once more the truth about post-hoc definitions:

  1. No post-hoc definition of the function that “paints” the function using the information from the specific details of what is observed is correct. Those definitions are clear examples of TSS fallacy.
  2. On the contrary, any post-hoc definition that simply recognizes a function which is related to an objectively existing property of the system, and makes no special use of the specific details of what is observed to “paint” the function, is perfectly correct. It is not a case of TSS fallacy.

 

b) The objection of the different possible levels of function definition.

DNA_Jock summed up this specific objection in the course of a long discussion in the thread about the English language:

Well, I have yet to see an IDist come up with a post-specification that wasn’t a fallacy. Let’s just say that you have to be really, really, really cautious if you are applying a post-facto specification to an event that you have already observed, and then trying to calculate how unlikely that specific event was. You can make the probability arbitrarily small by making the specification arbitrarily precise.

OK, I have just discussed why post-specifications are not in themselves a fallacy. Let’s say that DNA_Jock apparently admits it, because he just says that we have to be very cautious in applying them. I agree with that, and I have explained what the caution should be about.

Of course, I don’t agree that ID’s post-hoc specifications are a fallacy. They are not, not at all.

And I absolutely don’t agree with his argument that one of the reasosn why ID’s post-hoc specifications are a fallacy would be that “You can make the probability arbitrarily small by making the specification arbitrarily precise.”

Let’s try to understand why.

So, let’s go back to our example 3), the wall with the green bricks and the aiming inference.

Let’s make our shooter a little less precise: let’s say that, out of 100 shots, only 50 hits are green bricks.

Now, the math becomes:

The probability of one succesful hit (where success means hitting a green brick) is still 0.01 (100/10000).

The probability of having 50 successes or more in 100 shots can be computed using the binomial distribution. It is:

6.165016e-72

Now, the system exhibits “only” 236 bits of functional information. Much less than in the previous example, but still more than enough, IMO, to infer aiming.

Consider that five sigma, which is ofetn used as a standard in physics to reject the nulll hypothesis , is just 3×10-7,  less than 22 bits.

Now, DNA_Jock’s objection would be that our post-hoc specification is not valid because “we can make the probability arbitrarily small by making the specification arbitrarily precise”.

But is that true? Of course not.

Let’s say that, in this case, we try to “make the specification arbitrarily more precise”, defining the function of sharp aiming as “hitting only green bricks with all 100 shots”.

Well, we are definitely “making the probability arbitrarily small by making the specification arbitrarily precise”. Indeed, we are making the specification more precise for about 128 orders of magnitude! How smart we are, aren’t we?

But if we do that, what happens?

A very simple thing: the facts that we are observing do not meet the specification anymore!

Because, of  course, the shooter hit only 50 green bricks out of 100. He is smart, but not that smart.

Neither are we smart if we do such a foolish thing, defining a function that is not met by observed facts!

The simple truth is: we cannot at all “make the probability arbitrarily small by making the specification arbitrarily precise”, as DNA_Jock argues, in our post-hoc specification, because otherwise our facts would not meet our specification anymore, and that would be completely useless and irrelevant..

What we can and must do is exactly what is always done in all cases where hypothesis testing is applied in science (and believe me, that happens very often).

We compute the probabilities of observing the effect that we are indeed observing, or a higher one, if we assume the null hypothesis.

That’s why I have said that the probability of “having 50 successes or more in 100 shots” is 6.165016e-72.

This is called a tail probability, in particular the probability of the upper tail. And it’s exactly what is done in science, in most scenarios.

Therefore, DNA_Jock’s argument is completely wrong.

c) The objection of the possible alternative solutions, and of the incomplete exploration of the search space.

c1) The premise

This is certainly the most complex point, because it depends critically on our understanding of protein functional space, which is far from complete.

For the discussion to be in some way complete, I have to present first a very general premise. Neo-darwinists, or at least the best of them, when they understand that they have nothing better to say,  usually desperately recur to a set of arguments related to the functional space of proteins. The reason is simple enough: as the nature and structure of that space is still not well known or understood, it’s easier to equivocate with false reasonings.

Their purpose, in the end, is always to suggest that functional sequences can be much more frequent than we believe. Or at least, that they are much more frequent than IDists believe. Because, if functional sequences are frequent, it’s certainly easier for RV to find them.

The arguments for this imaginary frequency of biological function are essentially of five kinds:

  1. The definition of biological function.
  2. The idea that there are a lot of functional islands.
  3. The idea that functional islands are big.
  4. The idea that functional islands are connected. The extreme form of this argument is that functional islands simply don’t exist.
  5. The idea that the proteins we are observing are only optimized forms that derive from simpler implementations through some naturally selectable ladder of simple steps.

Of course, different mixtures of the above arguments are also frequently used.

OK. let’s get rid of the first, which is rather easy. Of course, if we define extremely simple biological functions, they will be relatively frequent.

For example, the famous Szostak experiment shows that  a weak affinity for ATP is relatively common in a random library; about 1 in 1011 sequences 80 AAs long.

A weak affinity for ATP is certainly a valid definition for a biological function. But it is a function which is at the same time irrelevant and non naturally selectable. Only naturally selectable functions have any interest for the neo-darwinian theory.

Moreover, most biological functions that we observe in proteins are extremely complex. A lot of them have a functional complexity beyond 500 bits.

So, we are only interested in functions in the protein space which are naturally selectable, and we are specially interested in functions that are complex, because those are the ones about which we make a design inference.

The other three points are subtler.

  1. The idea that there are a lot of functional islands.

Of course, we don’t know exactly how many functional islands exist in the protein space, even restricting the concept of function to what was said above. Neo-darwinists hope that there are a lot of them. I think there are many, but not so many.

But the problem, again, is drastically redimensioned if we consider that not all functional islands will do. Going back to point 1, we need naturally selectable islands. And what can be naturally selected is much less than what can potentially be functional. A naturally selectable island of function must be able to give a reproductive advantage. In a system that already has some high complexity, like any living cell, the number of functions that can be immediately integrated in what already exists, is certainly strongly constrained.

This point is also stricly connected to the other two points, so I will go on with them and then try some synthesis.

  1. The idea that functional islands are big.

Of course, functional islands can be of very different sizes. That depends on how many sequences, related at sequence level (IOWs, that are part of the same island), can implement the function.

Measuring functional information in a sequence by conservation, like in the Dustron method or in my procedure many times described, is an indirect way of measuring the size of a functional island. The greater is the functional complexity of an island, the smaller is its size in the search space.

Now, we must remember a few things. Let’s take as an example an extremely conserved but not too long sequence, our friend ubiquitin. It’s 76 AAs long. Therefore, the associated search space is 20^76: 328 bits.

Of course, even the ubiquitin sequence can tolerate some variation, but it is still one of the most conserved sequences in evolutionary history. Let’s say, for simplicity, that at least 70 AAs are stictly conserved, and that 6 can vary freely (of course, that’s not exact, just an approximation for the sake of our discussion).

Therefore, using the absolute information potential of 4.3 bits per aminoacid, we have:

Functional information in the sequence = 303 bits

Size of the functional island = 328 – 303 = 25 bits

Now, a functional island of 25 bits is not exactly small: it corresponds to about 33.5 million sequences.

But it is infinitely tiny if compared to the search space of 328 bits:  7.5 x 10^98 sequences!

If the sequence is longer, the relationship between island space and search space (the ocean where the island is placed) becomes much worse.

The beta chain of ATP synthase (529 AAs), another old friend, exhibits 334 identities between e. coli and humans. Always for the sake of simplicity, let’s consider that about 300 AAs are strictly conserved, and let’s ignore the functional contraint on all the other AA sites. That gives us:

Search space = 20^529 = 2286 bits

Functional information in the sequence = 1297 bits

Size of the functional island =  2286 – 1297 = 989 bits

So, with this computation, there could be about 10^297 sequences that can implement the function of the beta chain of ATP synthase. That seems a huge number (indeed, it’s definitley an overestimate, but I always try to be generous, especially when discussing a very general principle). However, now the functional island is 10^390 times smaller than the ocean, while in the case of ubiquitin it was “just”  10^91 times smaller.

IOWs, the search space (the ocean) increases exponentially much more quickly than the target space (the functional island) as the lenght of the functional sequence increases, provided of course that the sequences always retain high functional information.

The important point is not the absolute size of the island, but its rate to the vastness of the ocean.

So, the beta chain of ATP synthase is really a tiny, tiny island, much smaller than ubiquitin.

Now, what would be a big island? It’s simple: a functional isalnd which can implement the same function at the same level, but with low functional information. The lower the functional information, the bigger the island.

Are there big islands? For simple functions, certainly yes. Behe quotes the antifreeze protein as an example example. It has rather low FI.

But are there big islands for complex functions, like that of ATP synthase beta chain? It’s absolutely reasonable to believe that there are none. Because the function here is very complex, and it cannot be implemented by a simple sequence, exactly like a functional spreadsheet software annot be written by a few bits of source code. Neo-darwinists will say that we don’t know that for certain. It’s true, we don’t know it for certain. We know it almost for certain.

The simple fact remains: the only example of the beta chain of the F1 complex of ATP synthase that we know of is extremely complex.

Let’s go, for the moment, to the 4th argument.

  1. The idea that functional islands are connected. The extreme form of this argument is that functional islands simply don’t exist.

This is easier. We have a lot of evidence that functional islands are not connected, and that they are indeed islands, widely isolated in the search space of possible sequences. I will mention the two best evidences:

4a) All the functional proteins that we know of, those that exist in all the proteomse we have examined, are grouped in abot 2000 superfamilies. By definition, a protein superfamily is a cluster of sequences that have:

  • no sequence similarity
  • no structure similarity
  • no function similarity

with all the other groups.

IOWs, islands in the sequence space.

4b) The best (and probably the only) good paper that relates an experiment where Natural Selection is really tested by an approrpiaite simulation is the rugged landscape paper:

Experimental Rugged Fitness Landscape in Protein Sequence Space

http://journals.plos.org/plosone/article?id=10.1371/journal.pone.0000096

Here, NS is correctly simulated in a phage system, because what is measured is infectivity, which in phages is of course strictly related to fitness.

The function studied is the retrieval of a partially damaged infectivity due to a partial random substitution in a protein linked to infectivity.

In brief, the results show a rugged landscape of protein function, where random variation and NS can rather easily find some low-level peaks of function, while the original wild-type, optimal peak of function cannot realistically be found, not only in the lab simulation, but in any realistic natural setting. I quote from the conclusions:

The question remains regarding how large a population is required to reach the fitness of the wild-type phage. The relative fitness of the wild-type phage, or rather the native D2 domain, is almost equivalent to the global peak of the fitness landscape. By extrapolation, we estimated that adaptive walking requires a library size of 1070 with 35 substitutions to reach comparable fitness.

I would recommend to have a look at Fig. 5 in the paper to have an idea of what a rugged landscape is.

However, I will happily accept a suggestion from DNA_Jock, made in one of his recent comments at TSZ about my Ubiquitin thread, and with which I fully agree. I quote him:

To understand exploration one, we have to rely on in vitro evolution experiments such as Hayashi et al 2006 and Keefe & Szostak, 2001. The former also demonstrates that explorations one and two are quite different. Gpuccio is aware of this: in fact it was he who provided me with the link to Hayashi – see here.
You may have heard of hill-climbing algorithms. Personally, I prefer my landscapes inverted, for the simple reason that, absent a barrier, a population will inexorably roll downhill to greater fitness. So when you ask:

How did it get into this optimized condition which shows a highly specified AA sequence?

I reply
It fell there. And now it is stuck in a crevice that tells you nothing about the surface whence it came. Your design inference is unsupported.

Of course, I don’t agree with the last phrase. But I fully agree that we should think of local optima as “holes”, and not as “peaks”. That is the correct way.

So, the protein landscape is more like a ball and holes game, but without a guiding labyrinth: as long as the ball in on the flat plane (non functional sequences), it can go in any direction, freely. However, when it falls into a hole, it will quickly go to the bottom, and most likely it will remain there.

 

 

But:

  • The holes are rare, and they are of different sizes
  • They are distant from one another
  • A same function can be implemented by different, distant holes, of different size

What does the rugged landscape paper tell us?

  • That the wildtype function that we observe in nature is an extremely small hole. To find it by RV and NS, according to the authors, we should start with a library of 10^70 sequences.
  • That there are other bigger holes which can partially implement some function retrieval, and that are in the range of reasonable RV + NS
  • That those simpler solutions are not bridges to the optimal solution observed in the wildtype. IOWs. they are different, and there is no “ladder” that NS can use to reach the optimal solution .

Indeed, falling into a bigger hole (a much bigger hole, indeed) is rather a severe obstacle to finding the tiny hole of the wildtype. Finding it is already almost impossible because it is so tiny, but it becomes even more impossible if the ball falls into a big hole, because it will be trapped there by NS.

Therefore, to sum up, both the existence of 2000 isolated protein superfamilies and the evidence from the rugged landscape paper demonstrate that functional islands exist, and that they are isolated in the sequence space.

Let’s go now to the 5th argument:

  1. The idea that the proteins we are observing are only optimized forms that derive from simpler implementations by a naturally selectable ladder.

This is derived from the previous argument. If bigger functional holes do exist for a function (IOWs, simpler implementations), and they are definitely easier to find than the optimal solution we observe, why not believe that the simpler solutions were found first, and then opened the way to the optimal solution by a process of gradual optimization and natural selection of the steps? IOWs, a naturally selectable ladder?

And the answer is: because that is impossible, and all the evidence we have is against that idea.

First of all, even if we know that simpler implementations do exist in some cases (see the rugged landscape paper), it is not at all obvious that they exist as a general rule.

Indeed, the rugged landscape experiment is a very special case, because it is about retrieval of a function that has been only partially impaired by substituting a random sequence to part of an already existing, functional protein.

The reason for that is that, if they had completely knocked out the protein, infectivity, and therefore survival itself, would not have survived, and NS could not have acted at all.

In function retrieval cases, where the function is however kept even if at a reduced level, the role of NS is greatly helped: the function is already there, and can be optimed with a few naturally selectable steps.

And that is what happens in the case of the Hayashi paper. But the function is retrieved only very partially, and, as the authors say, there is no reasonable way to find the wildtype sequence, the optimal sequence, in that way. Because the optimal sequence would require, according to the authors, 35 AA substitutions, and a starting library of 10^70 random sequences.

What is equally important is that the holes found in the experiment are not connected to the optimal solution (the wildtype). They are different from it at sequence level.

IOWs, this bigger holes do not lead to the optimal solution. Not at all.

So, we have a strange situation: 2000 protein superfamilies, and thousand and tousands of proteins in them, that appear to be, in most cases, extremely functional, probably absolutely optimal. But we have absolutely no evidence that they have been “optimized”. They are optimal, but not necessarily optimized.

Now, I am not excluding that some optimization can take place in non design systems: we have good examples of that in the few known microevolutionary cases. But that optimization is always extremely short, just a few AAs substitutions once the starting functional island has been found, and the function must already be there.

So, let’s say that if the extremely tiny functional island where our optimal solution lies, for example the wildtype island in the rugged landscape experiment, can be found in some way, then some small optimization inside that functional island could certainly take place.

But first, we have to find that island: and for that we need 35 specific AA substitutions (about 180 bits), and 10^70 starting sequences, if we go by RV + NS. Practically impossible.

But there is more. Do those simpler solutions always exist? I will argue that it is not so in the general case.

For example, in the case of the alpha and beta chains of the F1 subunit of ATP synthase, there is no evidence at all that simpler solutions exist. More on that later.

So, to sum it up:

The ocean of the search space, according to the reasonings of neo-darwinists, should be overflowing with potential naturally selectable functions. This is not true, but let’s assume for a moment, for the sake of discussion, that it is.

But, as we have seen, simpler functions or solutions, when they exist, are much bigger functional islands than the extremely tiny functional islands corresponding to solutions with high functional complexity.

And yet, we have seen that there is absolutely no evidence that simpler solutuion, when they exist, are bridges, or ladder, to highly complex solutions. Indeed, there is good evidence of the contrary.

Given those premises, what would you expect if the neo-darwinian scenario were true? It’s rather simple: an universal proteome overflowing with simple functional solutions.

Instead, what do we observe? It’s rather simple: an universal proteome overflowing with highly functional, probably optimal, solutions.

IOWs, we find in the existing proteome almost exclusively highly complex solutions, and not simple solutions.

The obvious conclusion? The neo-darwinist scenario is false. The highly functional, optimal solutions that we observe can only be the result of intentional and intelligent design.

c2) DNA_Jock’s arguments

Now I will take in more detail DNA_Jock’ s two arguments about alternative solutions and the partial exploration of the protein space, and will explain why they are only variants of what I have already discussed, and therefore not valid.

The first argument, that we can call “the existence of alternative solutions”, can be traced to this statement by DNA_Jock:

Every time an IDist comes along and claims that THIS protein, with THIS degree of constraint, is the ONLY way to achieve [function of interest], subsequent events prove them wrong. OMagain enjoys laughing about “the” bacterial flagellum; John Walker and Praveen Nina laugh about “the” ATPase; Anthony Keefe and Jack Szostak laugh about ATP-binding; now Corneel and I are laughing about ubiquitin ligase: multiple ligases can ubiquinate a given target, therefore the IDist assumption is false. The different ligases that share targets ARE “other peaks”.
This is Texas Sharp Shooter.

We will debate the laugh later. For the moment, let’s see what the argument states.

It says: the solution we are observing is not the only one. There can be others, in some cases we know there are others. Therefore, your computation of probabilities, and therefore of functional inpormation, is wrong.

Another way to put it is to ask the question: “how many needles are there in the haystack?”

Alan Fox seems to prefer this metaphor:

This is what is wrong with “Islands-of-function” arguments. We don’t know how many needles are in the haystack. G Puccio doesn’t know how many needles are in the haystack. Evolution doesn’t need to search exhaustively, just stumble on a useful needle.

They both seem to agree about the “stumbling”. DNA_Jock says:

So when you ask:

How did it get into this optimized condition which shows a highly specified AA sequence?

I reply
It fell there. And now it is stuck in a crevice that tells you nothing about the surface whence it came.

OK, I think the idea is clear enough. It is essentially the same idea as in point 2 of my general premise. There are many functional islands. In particular, in this form, many functional islands for the same function.

I will answer it in two parts:

  • Is it true that the existence of alternative solutions, if they exist, makes the computation of functional complexity wrong?
  • Have we really evidence that alternative solutions exist, and of how frequent they can really be?

I will discuss the first part here, and say something about the second part later in the OP.

Let’s read again the essence of the argument, as summed up by me above:

” The solution we are observing is not the only one. There can be others, in some cases we know there are others. Therefore, your computation of probabilities, and therefore of functional information, is wrong.”

As it happens with smart arguments (and DNA_Jock is usually smart), it contains some truth, but is essentially wrong.

The truth could be stated as follows:

” The solution we are observing is not the only one. There can be others, in some cases we know there are others. Therefore, our computation of probabilities, and therefore of functional information, is not completely precise, but it is essentially correct”.

To see why that is the case, let’s use again a very good metaphor: Paley’s old watch. That will help to clarify my argument, and then I will discuss how it relies to proteins, in particular.

So, we have a watch. Whose function is to measure time. And, in general, let’s assume that we infer design for the watch, because its functional information is high enough to exclude that it could appear in any non design system spontaneously. I am confident that all reasonable people will agree with that. Anyway, we are assuming it for the present discussion.

 

 

Now, after having made a design inference (a perfectly correct inference, I would say) for this object, we have a sudden doubt. We ask ourselves: what if DNA_Jock is right?

So, we wonder: are there other solutions to measure time? Are there other functional islands in the search space of material objects?

Of course there are.

I will just mention four clear examples: a sundial, an hourglass, a digital clock,  an atomic clock.

The sundial uses the position of the sun. The hourglass uses a trickle of sand. The digital clock uses an electronic oscillator that is regulated by a quartz crystal to keep time. An atomic clock uses an electron transition frequency in the microwave, optical, or ultraviolet region.

None of them uses gears or springs.

Now, two important points:

  • Even if the functional complexity of the five above mentioned solutions is probably rather different (the sundial and the hourglass are probably quite simpler, and the atomic clock is probably the most complex), they are all rather complex. None of them would be easily explained without a design inference. IOWs, they are small functional islands, each of them. Some are bigger, some are really tiny, but none of them is big enough to allow a random origin in a non design system.
  • None of the four additional solutions mentioned would be, in any way, a starting point to get to the traditional watch by small functional modifications. Why? Because they are completely different solutions, based on different ideas and plans.

If someone believes differently, he can try to explain in some detail how we can get to a traditional watch starting from an hourglass.

 

 

Now, an important question:

Does the existence of the four mentioned alternative solutions, or maybe of other possible similar solutions, make the design inference for the traditional watch less correct?

The answer, of course, is no.

But why?

It’s simple. Let’s say, just for the sake of discussion, that the traditional watch has a functional complexity of 600 bits. There are at least 4 additional solutions. Let’s say that each of them has, again, a functional complexity of 500 bits.

How much does that change the probability of getting the watch?

The answer is: 2 bits (because we have 4 solutions instead of one). So, now the probability is 598 bits.

But, of course, there can be many more solutions. Let’s say 1000. Now the probability would be about 590 bits. Let’s say one million different complex solutions (this is becoming generous, I would say). 580 bits. One billion? 570 bits.

Shall I go on?

When the search space is really huge, the number of really complex solutions is empirically irrelevant to the design inference. One observed complex solution is more than enough to infer design. Correctly.

We could call this argument: “How many needles do you need to tranfsorm a haystack into a needlestack?” And the answer is: really a lot of them.

Our poor 4 alternative solutions will not do the trick.

But what if there are a number of functional islands that are much bigger, much more likely? Let’s say 50 bits functional islands. Much simpler solutions. Let’s say 4 of them. That would make the scenario more credible. Not so much, probably, but certainly it would work better than the 4 complex solutions.

OK, I have already discussed that above, but let’s say it again. Let’s say that you have 4 (or more) 50 bits solution, and one (or more) 500 bits solution. But what you observe as a fact is the 500 bits solution, and none of the 50 bits solutions. Is that credible?

No, it isn’t. Do you know how smaller a 500 bits solution is if compared to a 50 bits solution? It’s 2^450 times smaller: 10^135 times smaller. We are dealing with exponential values here.

So, if much simpler solutions existed, we would expect to observe one of them, and not certainly a solution that is 10^135 times more unlikely. The design inference for the highly complex solution is not disturbed in any way by the existence of much simpler solutions.

OK, I think that the idea is clear enough.

c3) The laughs

As already mentioned, the issue of alternative solutions and uncounted needles seems to be a special source of hilarity for DNA_Jock.  Good for him (a laugh is always a good thing for physical and mental health). But are the laughs justified?

I quote here again his comment about the laughs, that I will use to analyze the issues.

Every time an IDist comes along and claims that THIS protein, with THIS degree of constraint, is the ONLY way to achieve [function of interest], subsequent events prove them wrong. OMagain enjoys laughing about “the” bacterial flagellum; John Walker and Praveen Nina laugh about “the” ATPase; Anthony Keefe and Jack Szostak laugh about ATP-binding; now Corneel and I are laughing about ubiquitin ligase: multiple ligases can ubiquinate a given target, therefore the IDist assumption is false. The different ligases that share targets ARE “other peaks”.

I will not consider the bacterial flagellum, that has no direct relevance to the discussion here. I will analyze, instead, the other three laughable issues:

  • Szostak and Keefe’s ATP binding protein
  • ATP synthase (rather than ATPase)
  • E3 ligases

Szostak and Keefe should not laugh at all, if they ever did. I have already discussed their paper a lot of times. It’s a paper about directed evolution which generates a strongly ATP binding protein form a weakly ATP binding protein present in a random library. It is directed evolution by mutation and artificial selection. The important point is that both the original weakly binding protein and the final strongly binding protein are not naturally selectable.

Indeed, a protein that just binds ATP is of course of no utility in a cellular context. Evidence of this obvious fact can be found here:

A Man-Made ATP-Binding Protein Evolved Independent of Nature Causes Abnormal Growth in Bacterial Cells

http://journals.plos.org/plosone/article?id=10.1371/journal.pone.0007385

There is nothing to laugh about here: the protein is a designed protein, and anyway it is no functional peak/hole at all in the sequence space, because it cannot be naturally selected.

Let’s go to ATP synthase.

DNA_Jock had already remarked:

They make a second error (as Entropy noted) when they fail to consider non-traditional ATPases (Nina et al).

And he gives the following link:

Highly Divergent Mitochondrial ATP Synthase Complexes in Tetrahymena thermophila

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC2903591/

And, of course, he laughs with Nina (supposedly).

OK. I have already discussed that the existence of one or more highly functional, but different, solutions to ATP building would not change the ID inference at all. But is it really true that there are these other solutions?

Yes and no.

As far as my personal argument is concerned, the answer is definitely no (or at least, there is no evidence of them). Why?

Because my argument, repeated for years, has always been based (everyone can check) on the alpha and beta chains of ATP synthase, the main constituents of the F1 subunit, where the true catalytic function is implemented.

To be clear, ATP synthase is a very complex molecule, made of many different chains and of two main multiprotein subunits. I have always discussed only the alpha and beta chains, because those are the chains that are really highly conserved, from prokaryotes to humans.

The other chains are rather conserved too, but much less. So, I have never used them for my argument. I have never presented blast values regarding the other chains, or made any inference about them. This can be checked by everyone.

Now, the Nina paper is about a different solution for ATP synthase that can be found in some single celled eukaryotes,

I quote here the first part of the abstract:

The F-type ATP synthase complex is a rotary nano-motor driven by proton motive force to synthesize ATP. Its F1 sector catalyzes ATP synthesis, whereas the Fo sector conducts the protons and provides a stator for the rotary action of the complex. Components of both F1 and Fo sectors are highly conserved across prokaryotes and eukaryotes. Therefore, it was a surprise that genes encoding the a and b subunits as well as other components of the Fo sector were undetectable in the sequenced genomes of a variety of apicomplexan parasites. While the parasitic existence of these organisms could explain the apparent incomplete nature of ATP synthase in Apicomplexa, genes for these essential components were absent even in Tetrahymena thermophila, a free-living ciliate belonging to a sister clade of Apicomplexa, which demonstrates robust oxidative phosphorylation. This observation raises the possibility that the entire clade of Alveolata may have invented novel means to operate ATP synthase complexes.

Emphasis mine.

As everyone can see, it is absolutely true that these protists have a different, alternative form of ATP symthase: it is based on a similar, but certainly divergent, architecture, and it uses some completely different chains. Which is certainly very interesting.

But this difference does not involve the sequence of the alpha and beta chains in the F1 subunit.

Beware, the a and b subunits mentioned above by the paper are not the alpha and beta chains.

From the paper:

The results revealed that Spot 1, and to a lesser extent, spot 3 contained conventional ATP synthase subunits including α, β, γ, OSCP, and c (ATP9)

IOWs, the “different” ATP synthase uses the same “conventional” forms of alpha and beta chain.

To be sure of that, I have, as usual, blasted them against the human forms. Here are the results:

ATP synthase subunit alpha, Tetrahymena thermophila, (546 AAs) Uniprot Q24HY8, vs  ATP synthase subunit alpha, Homo sapiens, 553 AAs (P25705)

Bitscore: 558 bits     Identities: 285    Positives: 371

ATP synthase subunit beta, Tetrahymena thermophila, (497 AAs) Uniprot I7LZV1, vs  ATP synthase subunit beta, Homo sapiens, 529 AAs (P06576)

Bitscore: 729 bits     Identities: 357     Positives: 408

These are the same, old, conventional sequences that we find in all organisms, the only sequences that I have ever used for my argument.

Therefore, for these two fundamental sequences, we have no evidence at all of any alternative peaks/holes. Which, if they existed, would however be irrelevant, as already discussed.

Not much to laugh about.

Finally, E3 ligases. DNA_Jock is ready to laugh about them because of this very good paper:

Systematic approaches to identify E3 ligase substrates

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5103871/

His idea, shared with other TSZ guys, is that the paper demonstrates that E3 ligases are not specific proteins, because a same substrate can bind to more than one E3 ligase.

The paper says:

Significant degrees of redundancy and multiplicity. Any particular substrate may be targeted by multiple E3 ligases at different sites, and a single E3 ligase may target multiple substrates under different conditions or in different cellular compartments. This drives a huge diversity in spatial and temporal control of ubiquitylation (reviewed by ref. [61]). Cellular context is an important consideration, as substrate–ligase pairs identified by biochemical methods may not be expressed or interact in the same sub-cellular compartment.

I have already commented elsewhere (in the Ubiquitin thread) that the fact that a substrate can be targeted by multiple E3 ligases at different sites, or in different sub-cellular compartments, is  clear evidence of complex specificity. IOWs, its’ not that two or more E3 ligases bind a same target just to do the same thing, they bind the same target in different ways and different context to do different things. The paper, even if very interesting, is only about detecting affinities, not function.

That should be enough to stop the laughs. However, I will add another simple concept. If E3 ligases were really redundant in the sense suggested by DNA_Jock and friends, their loss of function should not be a serious problem for us. OK, I will just quote a few papers (not many, because this OP is already long enough):

The multifaceted role of the E3 ubiquitin ligase HOIL-1: beyond linear ubiquitination.

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/26085217

HOIL-1 has been linked with antiviral signaling, iron and xenobiotic metabolism, cell death, and cancer. HOIL-1 deficiency in humans leads to myopathy, amylopectinosis, auto-inflammation, and immunodeficiency associated with an increased frequency of bacterial infections.

WWP1: a versatile ubiquitin E3 ligase in signaling and diseases.

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/22051607

WWP1 has been implicated in several diseases, such as cancers, infectious diseases, neurological diseases, and aging.

RING domain E3 ubiquitin ligases.

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/19489725

RING-based E3s are specified by over 600 human genes, surpassing the 518 protein kinase genes. Accordingly, RING E3s have been linked to the control of many cellular processes and to multiple human diseases. Despite their critical importance, our knowledge of the physiological partners, biological functions, substrates, and mechanism of action for most RING E3s remains at a rudimentary stage.

HECT-type E3 ubiquitin ligases in nerve cell development and synapse physiology.

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/25979171

The development of neurons is precisely controlled. Nerve cells are born from progenitor cells, migrate to their future target sites, extend dendrites and an axon to form synapses, and thus establish neural networks. All these processes are governed by multiple intracellular signaling cascades, among which ubiquitylation has emerged as a potent regulatory principle that determines protein function and turnover. Dysfunctions of E3 ubiquitin ligases or aberrant ubiquitin signaling contribute to a variety of brain disorders like X-linked mental retardation, schizophrenia, autism or Parkinson’s disease. In this review, we summarize recent findings about molecular pathways that involve E3 ligasesof the Homologous to E6-AP C-terminus (HECT) family and that control neuritogenesis, neuronal polarity formation, and synaptic transmission.

Finally I would highly recommend the following recent paper to all who want to approach seriously the problem of specificity in the ubiquitin system:

Specificity and disease in the ubiquitin system

https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5264512/

Abstract

Post-translational modification (PTM) of proteins by ubiquitination is an essential cellular regulatory process. Such regulation drives the cell cycle and cell division, signalling and secretory pathways, DNA replication and repair processes and protein quality control and degradation pathways. A huge range of ubiquitin signals can be generated depending on the specificity and catalytic activity of the enzymes required for attachment of ubiquitin to a given target. As a consequence of its importance to eukaryotic life, dysfunction in the ubiquitin system leads to many disease states, including cancers and neurodegeneration. This review takes a retrospective look at our progress in understanding the molecular mechanisms that govern the specificity of ubiquitin conjugation.

Concluding remarks

Our studies show that achieving specificity within a given pathway can be established by specific interactions between the enzymatic components of the conjugation machinery, as seen in the exclusive FANCL–Ube2T interaction. By contrast, where a broad spectrum of modifications is required, this can be achieved through association of the conjugation machinery with the common denominator, ubiquitin, as seen in the case of Parkin. There are many outstanding questions to understanding the mechanisms governing substrate selection and lysine targeting. Importantly, we do not yet understand what makes a particular lysine and/or a particular substrate a good target for ubiquitination. Subunits and co-activators of the APC/C multi-subunit E3 ligase complex recognize short, conserved motifs (D [221] and KEN [222] boxes) on substrates leading to their ubiquitination [223–225]. Interactions between the RING and E2 subunits reduce the available radius for substrate lysines in the case of a disordered substrate [226]. Rbx1, a RING protein integral to cullin-RING ligases, supports neddylation of Cullin-1 via a substrate-driven optimization of the catalytic machinery [227], whereas in the case of HECT E3 ligases, conformational changes within the E3 itself determine lysine selection [97]. However, when it comes to specific targets such as FANCI and FANCD2, how the essential lysine is targeted is unclear. Does this specificity rely on interactions between FA proteins? Are there inhibitory interactions that prevent modification of nearby lysines? One notable absence in our understanding of ubiquitin signalling is a ‘consensus’ ubiquitination motif. Large-scale proteomic analyses of ubiquitination sites have revealed the extent of this challenge, with seemingly no lysine discrimination at the primary sequence level in the case of the CRLs [228]. Furthermore, the apparent promiscuity of Parkin suggests the possibility that ubiquitinated proteins are the primary target of Parkin activity. It is likely that multiple structures of specific and promiscuous ligases in action will be required to understand substrate specificity in full.

To conclude, a few words about the issue of the sequence space not entirely traversed.

We have 2000  protein superfamilies that are completely unrelated at sequence level. That is  evidence that functional protein sequences are not bound to any particular region of the sequence space.

Moreover, neutral variation in non coding and non functional sequences can go any direction, without any specific functional constraints. I suppose that neo-darwinists would recognize that parts of the genomes is non functional, wouldn’t they? And we have already seen elsewhere (in the ubiquitin thread discussion) that many new genes arise from non coding sequences.

So, there is no reason to believe that the functional space has not been traversed. But, of course, neutral variation can traverse it only at very low resolution.

IOWs, there is no reason that any specific part of the sequence space is hidden from RV. But of course, the low probabilistic resources of RV can only traverse different parts of the sequence space occasionally.

It’s like having a few balls that can move freely on a plane, and occasionally fall into a hole. If the balls are really few and the plane is extremely big, the balls will be able to  potentially traverse all the regions of the plane, but they will pass only through a very limited number of possible trajectories. That’s why finding a very small hole will be almost impossible, wherever it is. And there is no reason to believe that small functional holes are not scattered in the sequence space, as protein superfamilies clearly show.

So, it’s not true that highly functional proteins are hidden in some unexplored tresure trove in the sequence space. They are there for anyone to find them, in different and distant parts of the sequence space, but it is almost impossible to find them through a random walk, because they are so small.

And yet, 2000 highly functional superfamilies are there.

Moreover, The rate of appearance of new suprefamilies is highest at the beginning of natural history (for example in LUCA), when a smaller part of the sequence space is likely to have been traversed, and decreases constantly, becoming extremely low in the last hundreds of million years. That’s not what you would expect if the problem of finding new functional islands were due to how much sequence space has been traversed, and if the sequence space were really so overflowing with potential naturally selectable functions, as neo-darwinists like to believe.

OK, that’s enough. As expected, this OP is very long. However, I think that it  was important to discuss all these partially related issues in the same context.

 

Comments
gpuccio, May the best argument win! And may the one that's wrong admit it!Nonlin.org
July 31, 2018
July
07
Jul
31
31
2018
07:43 AM
7
07
43
AM
PDT
Nonlin.org: "So, let’s debate reality and facts!" Been there, done that. "Btw, you are much closer to Darwin than I am" I have no problems in being "close" to Darwin, or anyone else, in the things about which they are right. "Don’t take my feedback as an attack" I don't. "but as a chance to improve your arguments" I always do that with all my interlocutors. Once. Maybe twice. "And I DO want you to succeed! " I just want to find what is true. "Heck, I don’t mind our Theistic Evolutionists friends succeeding if it turns out they are right and I am wrong." Should I bet? You are both wrong! :) Frankly, I appreciate your goodwill and honesty, but I don't believe we can have an interesting intellectual confrontation. We have tried. There is nothing to add.gpuccio
July 27, 2018
July
07
Jul
27
27
2018
01:37 PM
1
01
37
PM
PDT
gpuccio, So, let's debate reality and facts! Btw, you are much closer to Darwin than I am since you accept Darwin's "natural selection" as true, despite the overwhelming evidence against: http://nonlin.org/natural-selection/ Don't take my feedback as an attack but as a chance to improve your arguments (feel free to return the favor). And I DO want you to succeed! Heck, I don't mind our Theistic Evolutionists friends succeeding if it turns out they are right and I am wrong. So bill cole on UD is colewd on TMZ! Good to know, but why the different name?Nonlin.org
July 27, 2018
July
07
Jul
27
27
2018
01:08 PM
1
01
08
PM
PDT
gpuccio
That argument is not in any way countered by Ewert’s ideas. Indeed, it is perfectly compatible with Ewert’s ideas, but it requires the addition of another important component: common descent. But it is perfectly possible to limit the idea of common descent to the common descent of modules.
Exactly. The idea is not a common descent vs common design all or nothing it is a better way to look at the data using design principles. Your ideas here are great and delivered so promptly :-)bill cole
July 27, 2018
July
07
Jul
27
27
2018
07:52 AM
7
07
52
AM
PDT
gpuccio "He certainly shares with them a strong, obstinate and almost obsessive dislike for reality and facts." He has got the TSZ guys running in circles. He pulled out a quote from UC Berkeley that UCD was a working assumption :-)bill cole
July 27, 2018
July
07
Jul
27
27
2018
07:48 AM
7
07
48
AM
PDT
bill cole: I think that our friend Nonlin.org would certainly be a perfect neo-darwinist, had his personal idiosincrasies crystallized differently. He certainly shares with them a strong, obstinate and almost obsessive dislike for reality and facts.gpuccio
July 27, 2018
July
07
Jul
27
27
2018
05:57 AM
5
05
57
AM
PDT
bill cole @480 I am proposing a better argument because I find Dembski's and gpuccio's arguments lacking as shown. Also, not all Darwinist claims are equally absurd. In this case, "absence of evidence is not evidence of absence". When gpuccio states: "We have a lot of evidence that functional islands are not connected, and that they are indeed islands", the "linked by yet unknown, uncreated, eternal and universal scientific laws" counterargument is actually quite reasonable.Nonlin.org
July 27, 2018
July
07
Jul
27
27
2018
05:48 AM
5
05
48
AM
PDT
bill cole: I have read the initial part of Ewert's paper, enough to understand clearly his ideas, even if I still ahve to go into the detail of the testing of the hypothesis. So, I can tell you what I think of the general idea expressed in the paper. My first comment is: I like the idea very much. I like the idea of the reuse of modules, and as you know it is definitely part of my general model: the engineering of biological organisms is certanly and obviously modular, definitely configuring OOP. Of course, I agree that common design is a major component of what we observe. Both in the case of one biological designer, or of many of them, common design is certainly there. And of course I also agree that functional constraints have an important role. Please, look at this recent comment of mine, written before I read Ewert's paper, and you will see that somne of those ideas are certainly part of my personal model: https://uncommondescent.com/intelligent-design/breaking-a-junk-dna-jumping-gene-is-critical-for-embryo-cell-development/#comment-662145 I also like the idea that a dependency graph can explain what we observe even better than a hyerarchical tree. That is definitely possible, and maybe likely. But... there is a but. The but is that Ewert uses these arguments to explain what we observe without using the idea of common descent. But, in reality, he is only countering the argument from nested hyerarchy. And, as you probably know, I have never really thought that the argument from nested hyerarchy is the real important argument for common descent. The important argument for common descent is another one: it is the signature of neutral variation in DNA and proteins. That argument is not in any way countered by Ewert's ideas. Indeed, it is perfectly compatible with Ewert's ideas, but it requires the addition of another important component: common descent. But it is perfectly possible to limit the idea of common descent to the common descent of modules. IOWs, the signature of neutral variation in biological molecules is very strong evidence for their physical continuity, IOWs for their physical descent. But it is perfectly possible that the descent is limited to re-used modules. In that way, a dependency graph would still be better than a tree. To be more clear: Ewert's model does not work if he assumes that modules are re-used only as programming schemes, without any physical derivation from what already exists. While that would explain the hyerarchy, it still would not explain the conservation of accruing neutral variation. Which is the strongest argument for common descent. But if we assume that modules are re-used physically, then it is perfectly possible that they are derived from multiple sources, according to a dependency graph, and not to a tree. The important point is that each module, when re-used, would still carry the signature of neutral variation according to the time it has existed, and has been exposed to it. That would explain both the hyerarchy and the neutral variation. The only way to counter the argument from neutral variation without assuming some form of physical descent would be to demonstrate that all variation is functionally constrained. But I think that, at present, facts are not pointing in that direction. Not at all.gpuccio
July 27, 2018
July
07
Jul
27
27
2018
04:36 AM
4
04
36
AM
PDT
gpuccio
Not yet. It seems interesting, and of course it’s a very hot topic. I will read it carefully as soon as possible.
Great. I think it is very complementary to the work you are doing :-). Took me about 3 passes to get my arms somewhat around it.bill cole
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
04:55 PM
4
04
55
PM
PDT
nonlin
Of course. All Darwinist arguments are “terrible…and… with no grounding in empirical science”.
So lets not change our arguments to avoid "just so" stories because they can do that no matter what our claims are.bill cole
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
04:53 PM
4
04
53
PM
PDT
gpuccio, Of course you disagree ...as anticipated. At least you are aware of the competing viewpoint.Nonlin.org
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
02:42 PM
2
02
42
PM
PDT
bill cole, Of course. All Darwinist arguments are "terrible...and... with no grounding in empirical science".Nonlin.org
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
02:34 PM
2
02
34
PM
PDT
bill cole: Not yet. It seems interesting, and of course it's a very hot topic. I will read it carefully as soon as possible.gpuccio
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
12:16 PM
12
12
16
PM
PDT
gpuccio Have you looked at Ewert's paper?bill cole
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
11:45 AM
11
11
45
AM
PDT
NonLin.
. Furthermore, ID opponents can easily counter the functional information argument with the claim that the ‘functional islands’ are linked by yet unknown, uncreated, eternal and universal scientific laws so that “evolution” jumps from island to island effectively reducing the search space from a ‘vast ocean’ to a manageable size.
This is a terrible counter argument with no grounding in empirical science.bill cole
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
11:44 AM
11
11
44
AM
PDT
Nonlin.org: I have read it. And I completely disagree. For reasons that we have already discussed. My position is simple enough: you are wrong, but there is no hope to have a discussion with you that is useful. That's all.gpuccio
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
10:05 AM
10
10
05
AM
PDT
gpuccio, You won't like this one bit, but should read it anyway as it is an alternative (I say 'better') to your analysis http://nonlin.org/intelligent-design/Nonlin.org
July 26, 2018
July
07
Jul
26
26
2018
08:27 AM
8
08
27
AM
PDT
gpuccio: I see your point. Thank you very much.OLV
June 9, 2018
June
06
Jun
9
09
2018
11:01 AM
11
11
01
AM
PDT
OLV: Yes, I had looked at that paper. Frankly, I find it rather confounding. The concept of molecular complexity is not very clear, and it is not clear how it relates to the problem of origin. The computation of informational complexity is not based on the function, and is therefore rather irrelevant for our perspective. I don't understand what type of practical application can be derived from the measures described in this paper. It just says that some structures are more complex than others, but it says so in terms of absolute complexity. Absolute compexity is interesting, but it is not a proper metrics that we can relate to explanatory theories.gpuccio
June 9, 2018
June
06
Jun
9
09
2018
09:10 AM
9
09
10
AM
PDT
gpuccio: Please, would you comment on this paper at your convenience? Maybe you already did it somewhere else, but I missed it. Thanks! https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5794832/#!po=0.704225OLV
June 9, 2018
June
06
Jun
9
09
2018
08:47 AM
8
08
47
AM
PDT
gpuccio, That's fine. No need to apologize. Thanks for helping me refine my argument. I honestly wished I could say your arguments make more sense :)Nonlin.org
June 4, 2018
June
06
Jun
4
04
2018
11:53 AM
11
11
53
AM
PDT
Nonlin.org: I am not frustrated, but I will not follow you along these lines of reasoning. I apologize in advance, but I really believe that what you say has no sense, and I have not further time to waste. Nothing personal, believe me. You have all my goodwill and, if you want, friendship. But enough is enough.gpuccio
June 2, 2018
June
06
Jun
2
02
2018
01:45 PM
1
01
45
PM
PDT
gpuccio@463 and 464 You skipped AGAIN over: “If you disagree, explain what is your “phenotype” and “environment”, and what in this infinite combination of infinities keeps you alive. And while at it calculate your “fitness” function too.” I will take your silence as an acceptance of my point about the unknowable infinite ‘phenotype’ and ‘environment’ and the meaningless of the “fitness” concept! I don’t see why a DNA change cannot be an adaptation even by your definition of ‘adaptation’ or by this other definition: “a change or the process of change by which an organism or species becomes better suited to its environment”. Also, many mutations come in groups and many are caused by mutagens – this clearly indicates their not-entirely-random nature (and again, DNA looks nothing like a fair coin/die to expect mutations to be random). I can see an adaptation algorithm accounting for ab-resistance, sickle cells, etc. as long as the goal is to try to save the species (not the individual). Of course this algorithm is not written in DNA because “DNA is not essence of life”, remember? You also say: “the resistance has been cleraly shown to depend of one or meore random mutations, which happen exactly with the frequencey that we expect from random mutations”. Because random generators are often incorporated in designed search algorithms, it doesn’t mean that what happens is necessarily random. We’re not just talking semantics here, the words and concepts behind them matter. My point was you will never know who is selected other than by looking at survival to which you reply with “It is differential survival”. But, since we’re all different, how can survival be anything other than “differential”? Also remember the example of the three organisms, all surviving or not regardless of their phenotype. What you call “selection” is nothing more than a retrospective story your brain builds - you do know the brain is very good at story telling, right? I know how pos/neg selection are supposed to happen. But we have seen that all mutations are tradeoffs including ab-resistance and sickle cell. How so? Because they don’t spread in the population but disappear instead when stimulus is removed. I also see them as adaptations and not “selection” per above. “Negative selection” is also problematic because: 1. It presupposes a standard but there is no human standard (pygmy, sumo wrestlers, bulimic, ADHD, epileptic, white, black, BRCA, Huntington, hairy, blue eyes, etc.) and if so, then no standard for any other organism either. So who deserves the “negative selection” treatment then? 2. You claim “many genetic disease become gradually more rare”, but where’s the evidence? Is this because humans take an active role in disease management? 3. Yes, many with “defective traits” die before reproduction …unless of course some farmer prefers them like that, or some scientist keeps them alive for study purpose :) …while killing their uninteresting ordinary cousins. “But this wouldn’t happen in nature”, right? Except the peacock, deer buck, etc. So how do we know they are “defective”? Because they die. And why do they die? Because they are “defective”. See? Circular logic, not “selection”. 4. This doesn’t follow and is confusing: “that’s why some proteins retain their sequences through long evolutionary times”. Again, this is the “just so” story telling brain at work. To summarize, your position is that “evolution” is true but partially guided? If so, I dispute the separation between guided and unguided and I dispute the unguided story. Sorry, I see your frustration, but my goal is to clarify the arguments and help all sides better understand what’s going on.Nonlin.org
June 2, 2018
June
06
Jun
2
02
2018
07:20 AM
7
07
20
AM
PDT
Mung: I am happy you like the metaphor! :) I don't use paperweights, but I do like them. :)gpuccio
June 1, 2018
June
06
Jun
1
01
2018
07:46 AM
7
07
46
AM
PDT
gpuccio:
The WT is the finely crafted paperweight. The solutions found in the Hayashi experiment are just stones.
:)Mung
June 1, 2018
June
06
Jun
1
01
2018
06:44 AM
6
06
44
AM
PDT
Nonlin.org at #460: "One more thing, what passes for “natural selection” is simply survival (disagree with proof if any)." I don't disagree. It is differential survival. "So what do you mean: “there is a lot of negative selection going on”?" Let's go back to the basics: a) Positive selection: it's what happens when a new trait, arisen by RV, has a reproductive advantage on the old trit in the population, so that gradually the new trait expands in the population and takes the place of the old trait, which is gradually eliminated, as a result of differential reproduction. This process exists, even if it is not so commen as darwinists believe. Antibiotic resistance of the simple type is a good example of positive selection. b) Negative selection: it's what happens when a functional trait is affected by some random variation that reduces significantly the functionality, and the reproductive rate. In this case, the new trait is subject to negative selection, and disappears, more or less gradually, while the old trait is conserved in the population. That's what happens all the time, each time that a deleterious mutation happens. That's how many genetic disease become gradually more rare, unless they are supported by other factors (like a high mutation rate at the specific site, or environmental factors like malaria for the sickle cell trait). That's why many babies with serious genetic diseases die when they are still very young. More generally, that's why some proteins retain their sequences thorugh long evolutionary times, while others change a lot. The proteins that are conserved have higher functional specificity in their sequences, and therefore most of the variation that happens is deleterious, and is eliminated. That's what is meant by the term negative (purifying) selection. I hope that is clear.gpuccio
May 31, 2018
May
05
May
31
31
2018
05:26 PM
5
05
26
PM
PDT
Nonlin.org at #459: I don't wnat to go on infinitely with you. I will try to address a few more points, but please, let's stop at some level! :) "Retrospective “explanations” are worthless since we cannot rerun natural experiments." I disagree. We can learn a lot from retrospective analyses, even if we cannot rerun experiments. We disagree on that. Let's stop it here. "You must explain this: “Disagree: the form of penicillin resistance that I mentioned is not an adaptation.”" An adaptation is a scenario where some pre-existing algorithm works upon information from outside, and uses it by some internal computation which generates a specific result. I think that plasmids in bacteria are adaptational tools, for example. So, when the penicillinase gene is passed from one kind of bacteria to another kind, because penicillin is in the environment, that's an adaptation. But in the case of simple penicillin resistance, the resistance has been cleraly shown to depend of one or meore random mutations, which happen exactly with the frequencey that we expect from random mutations, and which have the power to modify an existing protein making the bacteria more resistant to the antibiotic. Nothing in tha scenatio has any feature of an adaptation. What happens is not, in any way, dependent on any defensive algorithm in bacteria. It depends only on RV and the resulting random reproductive advantage in that specific environment. By the way, this is an "experiment of nature" which can be easily rerun in the lab. "Now you disagree even when you agree (on DNA)" I disagree that your statement is any criticism to something that I have said. "‘Selection’ is the wrong word. No one selects phenotypes except humans, and even that is different than the Darwinian story. All other simply seek to survive including the predators that just need to eat. Why would ‘seeking food’ and ‘defending oneself’ be called “selection”? It makes no sense whatsoever." I can agree that the word is not perfect, but that's how the process is usually called. I have no problems with words, and I accept the current use of words, provided that definitions are clear. I have said very clearly what I mean by "NS", and it's the same thing that darwinists mean. Of course, we deeply disagree about what that "thing" can really do! :) You don't like that it is called "selection". I have no problems with that. Let's say that, with you, we will call it "Anna", from now on. With others, I think I will go on with NS. My only interest is to distinguish between NS (which happens in a system without any design interventions) and Intelligent selection, or Artificial selection (they are the same thing for me), which only happens as a result of a conscious intelligent design intervention. Then you go on speaking of Intelligent selection, and how the evolution of species can only be the result of design. I agree. So, what's the problem? "There is no natural “selection” either. " I disagree on this and on everything that follows. Positive natural selection exists, and that can be easily demonstrated. Again, why is sicke cell triat so much more common in malaria regions? I agree that positive selection is limited, that it is not so generally important as darwinists think, and that it act usually on simple traits (like sickle cell disease). But I disagree that it does not exist. We definitely disagree on that. Let's stop it here.gpuccio
May 31, 2018
May
05
May
31
31
2018
05:15 PM
5
05
15
PM
PDT
Mung: Let's go to Corneel. He seems offended that I give more credit to Joe Felsestein than I give to him. But, unfortunately, that's the law of free market! :) It's not my fault if I find his argument generally boring and wrong. I have not the time to read everything that is writeen at TSZ. Lately, I have only looked at Joe Felsestein's posts, because he had started a rather well argumented thread about my arguments. I admit that I have only given a superficial look at all the other posts, catching something randomly, or only when some friend quoted them here. Again, it's a free market. But, as I have been led by you (Mung) to this post of him (Corneel), I will consider the Wesel statement there, and the two questions that he provides at the end of it about other issues. He says: Anyway, I am perfectly aware that the target string is being evaluated to find the number of matches, but I don’t see why that would prevent us from calculating the functional information of the resulting strings, which is what the whole exercise is about. Because the whole exercise is stupid. And I am being very generous here. If the string is alredy in the system, the simplest way to get it in a random string is to substitute each letter in the initial random string with the right letter from the target. That requires only as many sibstitutions as the string is ling. Or, if you have a printer at hand, you can simple print the target by a single click. Does Corneel really believe that if I have a file with a Shakespeare sonnet, and I print 10 copies of it, I am generating new functional information, indeed 10 times the original functional information. If he really believes that, he is completely out of reach, and cannot be saved in any way. Let's go to the two unrelated questions.
I am very interested whether cnidarians have a functional copy of TRIM62 for example, and how they pull that off without all the conserved information that humans have.
First question: "I am very interested whether cnidarians have a functional copy of TRIM62 for example" Answer: The best hit in Cnidaria is 84.7 bits, and the lowest among the first 100 hits is 54.3 bits. The E-values are 2e-16 for the best hit, 8e-07 for the lowest. Not much, but enough to detect homology, due mainly to the RING finger domain. The proteins involved are labeled as: "tripartite motif-containing protein 3-like [Stylophora pistillata]" or: "E3 ubiquitin-protein ligase TRIM71-like [Stylophora pistillata]" or: "RING finger protein nhl-1 [Exaiptasia pallida]" and so on. So, to answer Corneel's question, TRIM 62 as we oberve it in humans, a 475 AAs long protein with about 1000 bits of total potential functional information in BLAST comparisions, is not present in cnidaria, even if a low homology can be detected with other proteins having a similar RING finger domain. As already said, TRIM 62 appears rather suddenly in cartilaginous fish: E3 ubiquitin-protein ligase TRIM62 [Rhincodon typus] with 823 bits of homology and 80% identities to the human protein. That's a jump indeed! Second question. "how they [cnidaria] pull that off without all the conserved information that humans have" Maybe I am missing the brilliant, subtle wisdom in this question. My simple answer is: because that protein is not needed in cnidaria. What's the problem? Here is a paper about TRIM 62 (aka DEAR1): DEAR1 is a Chromosome 1p35 Tumor Suppressor and Master Regulator of TGF?-Driven Epithelial-Mesenchymal Transition https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC4107927/ And here is the OMIM page about the protein: https://www.omim.org/entry/616755 Now, I would suggest an idea to Corneel, hoping that it is not too devastating for his worldview: Is it possible, maybe, that cnidaria are functionally different from vertebrates? Let's see what he thinks.gpuccio
May 31, 2018
May
05
May
31
31
2018
04:56 PM
4
04
56
PM
PDT
Mung: It was not "a stated goal of the experiment to reproduce the wild-type or even to reach one with a comparable level of infectivity.” But the aim of the study was certainly to verify if they could achieve "improvement in phage infectivity" thorugh their model of RV + NS. They also admit that the wildtype is more or less at the peak of the functional space. Certainly, they wanted to verify if that peak could be reache. Otherwise, why the discussion about the practical impossibility of reaching it? Rumraket then goes on:
Of course it matters where you start, as that has significant implications for what level of function is in the immediate sequence neighborhood. The probability of finding mutations that sit on a slope that leads to levels of infectivity comparable to the wild-type is directly related to where that random initial location is. If you start with a completely dissimilar sequence that has zero similarity to the wild type, and if that sequence happens to sit close to the base of an entirely different hill from the one occupied by the wild-type sequence, then there’s no way selection is going to be able to climb to that other WT-hill, as it will obviously just crawl up the local hill rather than go down and start randomly walking through a neutral or deleterious space. In fact given that Gpuccio accepts DNA_Jocks “holes” rather than hills metaphor it should be obvious that the starting position is critical for what hole the protein will fall into. And if that local hill isn’t as tall as the WT hill, then it’s just stuck there.
Again, he does not understand the problem. If you start with any random sequence that is unrelated at sequence level to the WT, you are as far from the wildtype hole as you can be. But the reason why you will never reach the WT is not that you could be near some other hole, and threfore you will necessarily fall into that hole. Rumracket is ignoring the simple fact that random mutations can quickly carry you away from any nearby "hole". In the Hatashi model, indeed, the effects of NS are always contrasted by neutral drift. If you have alredy fallen into a hole, so that the effect of negative NS is very strong, it will probably overwhelm the effect of drift in most cases (but not in all). But in all other cases, the sequence is completely free to diverge in ant possible direction, especially when it is in near neutral territory. The true reason why you will never find the WT isalnd is because it is too small. Being an highly specific functional island, it is much more unlikely and much smalòler than the big, generic functional islands that were found in the experiment. It requires more specific AA positions (35, according to an estimate by the authors). It has higher FI. That's why you need 10^70 starting sequences to have a good probability of finding it. The holes, or hills, as you like, that were found in the experiment are gross, imperfect solutions, based on some generic resemblance to the WT solution. That's why they can be easily found. They are like the weak ATP binding in Szostak's paper. Weak bindings, imperfect solutions, are much more common in the functional space. It's only higly specific solutions that are extremely rare and extremely small islands, because that have much higher FI. So, it's easy to find a stone that we can use as a paperweight, but a refined, elegant and finely crafted paperweight is certainly designed. The WT is the finely crafted paperweight. The solutions found in the Hayashi experiment are just stones. And there is absolutely no evidence that the WT is a pinnacle with a large functional base that gradually leads to it: no evidence at all, except in the arbitrary drawins at TSZ. If that were the case, it would be easy to find it: we should only find the large base, and NS would do the rest. But in that case, it should be found with the same facility as the other gross solutions are found. There should be no necessiy of 10^70 starting sequences to find it! Therefore, it's a pinnacle. Period. He also says:
But as I have stated now like twenty times, the fact that random proteins seem to invariaby sit near hills that selection can climb (or “holes” for the protein to “fall” into) implies that the infectivity function is ubiquitous in sequence space.
It is not true. Random proteins do not "invariably" sit near hills that selection can climb. In the Szostak experiment, omly a couple out of 10^11 was sitting in such a position. Moreover, please note how he is, intentionally, using the word "selection" here, and not "NS". In the case of Szostak, it was not NS at all. In the case of Hayashi, it was NS indeed. But, as I have explained, the experiment was modeled exactly so that those gross results could be easily obtained. Why? Because it was an experiment of function retrieval, with the function still present, so that NS could already work on it. IOWs, they "damaged" a function, but not completely, so that it was easy to find soultions, simple solutions, that could partiall "repair" the damage, as you can partially improve a bump in the body of your car using a hammer. But you have to change the body part with a new one if you want a real repair. If the "holes" found by Hayashi were real solutions, then why the tweaking by NS did stop at low levels of function? Why did'n it reach functional levels similar to the WT? The simple answer is: because those holes-hills were gross, simple solutions, with no relationship to the refined, functional solution that is the WT. Then he says:
The proportion of holes that go as deep as the one occupied by the wild-type protein is actually a diversion.
No, it's really the problem. The problem is that practically all that we observe in nature is a refined, highly functional solution, involving a lot of functional complexity. And that those highly refined solutions are not, in any way, a gradual tweaking of generic, gross, common simple solutions which have almost no functional relevance at all, and that are not naturally selectable, except in experiments conceived for that, like the Hayashi experiment. IOWs, the weak ATP binding of Szostak would never, never lead to the (useless) high ATP binding in the final Szostak's protein. Why? Simply because the weak ATP binding would never be natuirally selected. NS has not ATP columns at its disposal to measure weak ATP binding in random sequences. So, the alpha or beta chains of ATP synthase, or the UBR5 E3 ligase, or any other example that I have discussed where the FU is extremely high, are not the tweaked gradual evolution of gross, simple sequences. Their function is complex and refined because of its same nature, exactly as a spreadsheet code is complex and refined because it is a spreadsheet, and no spreadsheet can be coded by 20 bits of code!gpuccio
May 31, 2018
May
05
May
31
31
2018
04:07 PM
4
04
07
PM
PDT
gpuccio@450 One more thing, what passes for “natural selection” is simply survival (disagree with proof if any). So what do you mean: “there is a lot of negative selection going on”?Nonlin.org
May 31, 2018
May
05
May
31
31
2018
12:41 PM
12
12
41
PM
PDT
1 2 3 17

Leave a Reply