Uncommon Descent Serving The Intelligent Design Community

Thomas Nagel vs. his critics: Has Neo-Darwinian evolution failed, and can teleological naturalism take its place?

Share
Facebook
Twitter
LinkedIn
Flipboard
Print
Email

It is not often that one’s opinion of a book improves after reading three negative reviews of it. I haven’t yet read Professor Thomas Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos: Why the Materialist Neo-Darwinian Conception of Nature is Almost Certainly False, but after reading what biologist H. Allen Orr, philosophers Brian Leiter and Michael Weisberg, and philosopher and ID critic Elliott Sober had to say about the book, I came away convinced that neo-Darwinism is an intellectual edifice resting on a foundation of sand… and sheer intellectual stubbornness on the part of its adherents. I do not wish to question the sincerity and learning of the reviewers, but I was deeply shocked by their unshakable attachment to Darwinism. Reading through the reviews, I was astonished to find the authors arguing that even if the origin of life should prove to be a fantastically improbable event that would not be expected to happen even once in the entire history of the cosmos, even if scientists are utterly unable to predict the general course of evolution, even if all attempts to reduce the science of biology to physics and chemistry are doomed to failure, even if it can be shown that we will never be able to explain consciousness in terms of physical processes, and even if neo-Darwinism proves to be incompatible with the existence of objective moral truths, such as “Killing people for fun is wrong,” we should still prefer Darwinism to any other account of origins, for to do otherwise is unscientific. I have to ask: whence such madness?

What these reviewers apparently fail to realize is that Charles Darwin himself would have conceded none of the “even ifs” conceded by his latter-day disciples. He realized, as they do not, that doing so would have severely undermined the credibility of his theory. Darwin believed in, and convinced his contemporaries of, the superiority of his theory of evolution by natural selection, largely because it claimed to provide an account of the development of life on Earth that was both predictable and progressive, and because it purported to explain the emergence of consciousness and our mental faculties in terms of underlying bodily processes. Interestingly, Darwin somehow managed to combine his thoroughly deterministic worldview with a belief in the objectivity of certain moral truths: throughout his life, he steadfastly maintained that slavery is wrong.

For the benefit of readers who may be wondering about Nagel’s account, I should say that he advocates a form of naturalistic teleology: that is, he believes that a purely historical explanation of the origin of life, consciousness and intelligence is doomed to failure; so, too, is a reductive explanation of these phenomena. We have to invoke final causes. Nagel is not religious; he does not believe that anything exists outside the natural realm. Nevertheless, he believes that it is a brute fact about Nature that it is biased towards the generation of life and consciousness. Because neo-Darwinism is an historical account of origins, which shuns forward-looking final causes and explains life within a reductionist framework, Nagel thinks it is almost certainly wrong – or at least, incomplete.

Professor Nagel’s espousal of teleological naturalism in his book, Mind and Cosmos has attracted a lot of criticism. In this essay, I’d like to address the main criticisms, one by one. My essay is divided into nine parts. Throughout this essay, all green highlights are mine.

1. Does the neo-Darwinian theory of evolution need to make predictions about the future, in order to qualify as a good scientific theory?
2. Is Darwinism tied to reductionism?
3. Does the plausibility of Darwinism depend on the origin of life and the emergence of consciousness and intelligence being unsurprising occurrences?
4. Do Nagel’s critics succeed in their attempt to render the origin of life unsurprising?
5. Is a teleological theory of Nature compatible with the scientific method?
6. Are there any good scientific arguments against Nagel’s teleological theory of Nature?
7. Could consciousness be a byproduct?
8. Faced with a choice between evolution and objective morality, which should we choose?
9. Neurath’s boat: does evolutionary naturalism undermine the validity of scientific reasoning?

1. Does the neo-Darwinian theory of evolution need to make predictions about the future, in order to qualify as a good scientific theory?

In his book, Mind and Cosmos, Professor Thomas Nagel argues that any evolutionary theory worth its salt should be able to retrospectively predict key events in the history of life (such as the emergence of consciousness) and show why these events were likely to occur. In their review of Nagel’s book, Professor Brian Leiter and Associate Professor Michael Weisberg attempt to rebut Thomas Nagel’s argument by insisting that a good scientific explanation does not need to make any predictions – a contentious claim that we’ll examine below. What I would like to do first is ask a simple question: what did Charles Darwin think about the role of prediction in scientific explanation?

(a) Darwin: a good scientific explanation has to invoke laws and be capable of making predictions

In his 1838 Essay on Theology and Natural Selection, Darwin insisted that any good scientific explanation had to be capable of making predictions – which is precisely what led him to reject creationism in the first place. Since the will of God is not subject to any law, it is unpredictable. For this reason, Darwin regarded theological explanations of biological diversity as scientifically useless:

N.B. The explanation of types of structure in classes – as resulting from the will of the deity, to create animals on certain plans, – is no explanationit has not the character of a physical law /& is therefore utterly useless. – it foretells nothing / because we know nothing of the will of the Deity, how it acts & whether constant or inconstant like that of man. – the cause given we know not the effect.
(Italics Darwin’s, bold emphases mine – VJT.)

What’s more, Darwin believed that any explanation of a phenomenon in terms of physical laws had to be a deterministic explanation: as he put it in his Autobiography, “Everything in nature is the result of fixed laws.” (Page 87, Nora Barlow’s 1958 edition.)

(b) According to Darwin, evolution is a deterministic process, whose broad trends are predictable over time

Darwin applied these rigorous methodological standards to his own theory: he envisaged evolution by natural selection as a thoroughly deterministic process, at least in its general outcomes. In his magnum opus, The Origin of Species, Darwin insisted that the current laws of Nature were sufficient to account for the origin of species, by natural processes:

If then the geological record be as imperfect as I believe it to be, and it may at least be asserted that the record cannot be proved to be much more perfect, the main objections to the theory of natural selection are greatly diminished or disappear. On the other hand, all the chief laws of palaeontology plainly proclaim, as it seems to me, that species have been produced by ordinary generation: old forms having been supplanted by new and improved forms of life, produced by the laws of variation still acting round us, and preserved by Natural Selection.
(The Origin of Species, 1st edition, 1859, Chapter X, p. 345.)

For Darwin, the course of evolution was not only fixed by deterministic laws; it was also predictable, at least in its broad outline. Darwin maintained that over the course of time, evolution tended to produce organisms that were more and more complex, in the degree of specialization of their body parts. In the concluding chapter to The Origin of Species, he argued that the evolution of life, viewed as a whole, was guaranteed by the laws of Nature to progress ever upward, and that the evolution of the “higher animals” was the inevitable outcome of simple biological laws:

And as natural selection works solely by and for the good of each being, all corporeal and mental endowments will tend to progress towards perfection. It is interesting to contemplate an entangled bank, clothed with many plants of many kinds, with birds singing on the bushes, with various insects flitting about, and with worms crawling through the damp earth, and to reflect that these elaborately constructed forms, so different from each other, and dependent on each other in so complex a manner, have all been produced by laws acting around us. These laws, taken in the largest sense, being Growth with Reproduction; Inheritance which is almost implied by reproduction; Variability from the indirect and direct action of the external conditions of life, and from use and disuse; a Ratio of Increase so high as to lead to a Struggle for Life, and as a consequence to Natural Selection, entailing Divergence of Character and the Extinction of less-improved forms. Thus, from the war of nature, from famine and death, the most exalted object which we are capable of conceiving, namely, the production of the higher animals, directly follows.
(1st edition, 1859, Chapter XIV, pp. 489-490.)

A critic might object that terms such as “progress,” “perfection,” “improved” and “higher” are scientifically vague, making them of little predictive value. However, Darwin was fully cognizant of this objection, and in his Descent of Man, he attempted to provide a rigorous definition of evolutionary progress:

The best definition of advancement or progress in the organic scale ever given, is that by Von Baer; and this rests on the amount of differentiation and specialisation of the several parts of the same being, when arrived, as I should be inclined to add, at maturity. Now as organisms have become slowly adapted by means of natural selection for diversified lines of life, their parts will have become, from the advantage gained by the division of physiological labour, more and more differentiated and specialised for various functions. The same part appears often to have been modified first for one purpose, and then long afterwards for some other and quite distinct purpose; and thus all the parts are rendered more and more complex. But each organism will still retain the general type of structure of the progenitor from which it was aboriginally derived. In accordance with this view it seems, if we turn to geological evidence, that organisation on the whole has advanced throughout the world by slow and interrupted steps.
(1st edition, 1871, Chapter VI, p. 211.)

On the Darwinian account, the evolution of animals’ body parts over the course of time is ultimately determined by the successive requirements imposed on them, as a result of changes in their environment, to which their ancestors had to adapt. The cumulative – and entirely predictable – result of such changes was the differentiation and specialization of living things’ bodily organs. The appearance of highly developed animals was thus the predictable outcome of simple biological laws operating over a period of billions of years.

(c) Leiter and Weisberg’s bold claim: a good scientific explanation doesn’t need to make any predictions

So it was with some surprise that I read Professor Brian Leiter and Associate Professor Michael Weisberg arguing in their review that a good scientific explanation does not need to make any predictions – even retrospective ones! For Leiter and Weisberg, the demand that scientific explanations should be able to make predictions is fundamentally misconceived:

Nagel endorses the idea that explanation and prediction are symmetrical: “An explanation must show why it was likely that an event of that type occurred.” In other words, to explain something is to be in a position to have predicted it if we could go back in time. He also writes, “To explain consciousness, a physical evolutionary history would have to show why it was likely that organisms of the kind that have consciousness would arise.” Indeed, he goes further, claiming that “the propensity for the development of organisms with a subjective point of view must have been there from the beginning.”

This idea, however, is inconsistent with the most plausible views about prediction and explanation, in both philosophy and science.

As we have seen, Darwin would have disagreed with this analysis: it was his dissatisfaction with the unpredictability of creation by Divine fiat that led him to search for a naturalistic alternative, and in the final paragraph of his Origin of Species, he declared that the evolution of the higher animals “directly follows” from the workings of the laws of Nature. In conceding the inability of the modern theory of evolution to make predictions about the future, Leiter and Weisberg are unknowingly depriving Darwin’s theory of one of its major selling points.

In any case, a careful reading of Leiter and Weisberg’s review leads me to conclude that their differences with Professor Thomas Nagel over the nature of scientific explanations are more apparent than real. What Leiter and Weisberg are denying is the need for scientific explanations to predict individual events, or to make predictions with certainty. Nagel could happily grant both these points. What he would deny, if I read him aright, is the possibility of a scientific explanation which doesn’t even make generic, probabilistic predictions. The theory of evolution must at least do that.

(d) Why probabilistic explanations don’t eliminate the need for predictions

Leiter and Weisberg attempt to bolster their claim that good scientific theories don’t need to be predictive, by an appeal to probabilistic reasoning:

Philosophers of science have long argued that explanation and prediction cannot be fully symmetrical, given the importance of probabilities in explaining natural phenomena. Moreover, we are often in a position to understand the causes of an event, but without knowing enough detail to have predicted it. For example, approximately 1 percent of children born to women over 40 have Down syndrome. This fact is a perfectly adequate explanation of why a particular child has Down syndrome, but it does not mean we could have predicted that this particular child would develop it.

But this argument fails to undermine Professor Nagel’s case. Even in the passage quoted by Leiter and Weisberg earlier, Nagel does not defend the extreme view that individual events are only properly explained when they can be predicted from their individual causes – which is why the Down syndrome example the authors cite completely misses the point. For Nagel, scientific explanation occurs at the generic level of the type rather than the individual token: as he puts it, “An explanation must show why it was likely that an event of that type occurred.” The perceptive reader will also notice that Nagel says “likely” rather than “certain.” Nagel is not espousing a rigid determinism here; he is merely insisting that a good explanation of consciousness must show that there was a significant likelihood of it emerging somewhere in the cosmos, over the course of time. Hardly an unreasonable request, one would have thought. For the past few decades, however, neo-Darwinists have lowered the bar: instead of demonstrating that life or consciousness had a mathematical likelihood of arising somewhere, they have been content to argue that life and consciousness may have arisen somewhere, because no law of Nature prohibits them from doing so. The trouble with explanations of this kind is that a scientific theory’s being able to explain the mere possibility of a specific effect does not make it a good theory. Unless that theory can assign a certain probability to that effect occurring within the time available, it is impossible to compare the theory with other scientific theories, in order to see which one does a better job of explaining the effect.

We might summarize this point under the slogan: “No quantification, no science.” At the present time, Darwin’s theory is poor at quantification, for all except the most trivial biological changes. When it comes to large-scale changes such as the emergence of consciousness, or even the formation of feathers or flagella, the hard numbers simply aren’t there: biologists have no probabilities to guide them – just guesswork.

2. Is Darwinism tied to reductionism?

Professor Richard Dawkins, an ardent defender of Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection. Like Darwin, Dawkins is an out-and-out reductionist. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

(a) Leiter and Weisberg’s astonishing claim: Darwin’s theory of evolution isn’t reductionist

In their review of Thomas Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos, Professors Leiter and Weisberg also make the astonishing claim that Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection is not committed in any way to reductionistic account of life or consciousness:

Nagel opposes two main components of the “materialist” view inspired by Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection. The first is what we will call theoretical reductionism, the view that there is an order of priority among the sciences, with all theories ultimately derivable from physics and all phenomena ultimately explicable in physical terms. We believe, along with most philosophers, that Nagel is right to reject theoretical reductionism, because the sciences have not progressed in a way consistent with it. We have not witnessed the reduction of psychology to biology, biology to chemistry, and chemistry to physics, but rather the proliferation of fields like neuroscience and evolutionary biology that explain psychological and biological phenomena in terms unrecognizable by physics. As the philosopher of biology Philip Kitcher pointed out some thirty years ago, even classical genetics has not been fully reduced to molecular genetics, and that reduction would have been wholly within one field. We simply do not see any serious attempts to reduce all the “higher” sciences to the laws of physics.

Yet Nagel argues in his book as if this kind of reductive materialism really were driving the scientific community…

Nagel here aligns himself, as best we can tell, with the majority view among both philosophers and practicing scientists. Just to take one obvious example, very little of the actual work in biology inspired by Darwin depends on reductive materialism of this sort; evolutionary explanations do not typically appeal to Newton’s laws or general relativity. Given this general consensus (the rhetoric of some popular science writing by Weinberg and others aside), it is puzzling that Nagel thinks he needs to bother attacking theoretical reductionism.

Leiter and Weisberg claim to speak for practicing scientists as well as philosophers, and they make the further claim that Darwinian biology doesn’t depend on reductionism. Both claims are highly contentious, to say the least.

(b) What Darwin’s leading defenders think about reductionism

The first thing that astonished me about this passage was that Professor Leiter and Weisberg were so ready – indeed, eager – to concede the failure of reductionism. Hardly any scientist or philosopher believes it nowadays, they claimed. This would definitely be news to Darwin’s modern-day bulldog, Professor Richard Dawkins, who has forcefully argued that all genuinely scientific explanations have to be reductive. On Dawkins’ view, a good explanation is one which simplifies that which it attempts to explain. To reject reductionism, on Dawkins’ view, is equivalent to saying that the complexity of life cannot be simplified. For Dawkins, that’s an admission of defeat. As he put it in an interview with Nick Pollard on February 28, 1995, which was published in the April 1995 edition of Third Way (vol 18 no. 3):

The whole scientific enterprise is aimed at explaining the world in terms of simple principles. We live in a world which is breathtakingly complicated, and we have a scientific theory – we have several – which enables us to see how that world could have come into being from very simple beginnings.

That’s what I call understanding. If I want to understand how a machine works, I want an explanation in terms of sub-units and even smaller sub-units, and finally I would get down to fundamental particles. That’s the kind of explanation which science aspires to give and is well on the way to giving.

Reductionist explanations are true explanations.

You really feel you’ve understood how a motor car works if you’ve been told how each of its bits work and how the bits move together to make the car work. Then you feel you’ve really got somewhere. But if somebody tried to explain the car in terms of – well, Julian Huxley satirised it as explaining a railway train by force locomotive – you would feel you had understood absolutely nothing.

But, it will be said, Dawkins is just one biologist. Very well, then; let us look at what another leading Darwin defender, Professor Jerry Coyne (author of the best-seller, Why Evolution is True) had to say about reductionism, in a recent post entitled, Is reductionism wrong?: a philosopher weighs in. Coyne composed this post in response to an opinion piece, entitled, Anything but Human (New York Times, August 5, 2012) by philosopher Richard Polt, professor and chair of philosophy at Xavier University, who criticized what he saw as the increasingly prevalent reductionist view that the human brain is basically a computer. In his reply, Coyne defended not only the brain-as-computer metaphor, but also the reductionist view that all of the emergent properties of any entity can, in principle, be reduced to the interaction of its parts:

Given that our brains evolved, why shouldn’t we assume that thinking and perceiving are essentially information processing. Yes, it’s a complicated form of processes, but what else could it be. And maybe now we can’t understand the whole in terms of its parts, and maybe aspects of our mentality, like consciousness, are emergent properties, but that doesn’t mean that they can’t ultimately, or in principle, be reduced to the interaction of parts. As far as we know, in all sciences emergent properties, like the behavior of gases or fluids, must be consistent with lower-level properties. There are no “top-down” properties that are not consistent with the interaction of parts.

I suspect that there are many modern biologists who would share Dawkins’ and Coyne’s views on reductionism. I therefore disagree with Leiter and Weisberg’s confident assertion that there is a “general consensus” in the scientific community that reductionism is false. I would like to ask: where is their evidence?

There is much that could be said in reply to Dawkins’ argument for reductionism. All I will say here is that scientific explanations need not involve a multi-level hierarchy of organization: sometimes, they invoke a single-level network of interacting, inter-dependent components. (Ecosystems are one case that immediately springs to mind; geological cycles are another.) Reductionism, then, is not essential to a good scientific explanation. On this point, Nagel is surely right.

Coyne’s argument is also flawed, because it trades on an equivocation. It is one thing to say that all of the “top-down” properties of an entity must be consistent with the interaction of its parts. It is quite another thing to say that the “top-down” properties of an entity must be determined by the interaction of its parts, as Coyne maintains. Only the second claim is reductionistic.

To illustrate the difference between the two claims, I’d like to give an example relating to free will. (I’m talking about libertarian free will here, which is what ordinary folk usually mean by the term.) Suppose that at the subatomic level, events occurring in our brains are subject to quantum effects, and that these effects are non-deterministic. It is easy to show that a non-deterministic system may be subject to specific constraints, while still remaining random. These constraints may be imposed externally, or alternatively, they may be imposed from above, as in top-down causation. To see how this might work, suppose that my brain performs the high-level act of making a choice, and that this act imposes a constraint on the quantum micro-states of tiny particles in my brain. This doesn’t violate quantum randomness, because a selection can be non-random at the macro level, but random at the micro level. The following two rows of digits will serve to illustrate my point.

1 0 0 0 1 1 1 1 0 0 0 1 0 1 0 0 1 1
0 0 1 0 0 0 0 1 1 0 1 1 0 1 1 1 0 1

The above two rows of digits were created by a random number generator. The digits in some of these columns add up to 0; some add up to 1; and some add up to 2.

Now suppose that I impose the non-random macro requirement: keep the columns whose sum equals 1, and discard the rest. I now have:

1 0 1 1 1 0 0 0 0 0 1
0 1 0 0 0 1 1 0 1 1 0

Each row is still random (at the micro level), but I have now imposed a non-random macro-level constraint on the system as a whole (at the macro level). That, I would suggest, what happens when I make a choice. Non-determinism, by itself, does not make us free in the libertarian sense; but top-down causation, acting on a non-deterministic system, makes genuine libertarian free will possible.

In this example, the entity in question is the human brain. The holistic “top-down” properties of the brain are quite consistent with the interaction of its non-deterministic subatomic parts; but they are not determined by the interaction of those parts: on the contrary, it is the whole that determines the parts, while preserving their randomness. Coyne’s argument fails to rule out holism; all it establishes is the rather trivial point that the activity of wholes is constrained (but not necessarily determined) by their parts.

(c) Was Charles Darwin a reductionist?

Charles Darwin shared the belief of the French physiologist Pierre Cabanis (1757-1808) that the human brain secretes thought just as the liver secretes bile.
Drawing of the human brain, showing several of the most important brain structures.
Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

The second thing that struck me about the above passage by Professors Leiter and Weisberg was that the authors were blissfully unaware that they were arguing against the views of Charles Darwin himself. Darwin’s account of the human mind was thoroughly mechanistic and reductionistic. In his Notebook C: Transmutation of species (2-7.1838), he wrote:

Why is thought, being a secretion of brain, more wonderful than gravity a property of matter? – It is our arrogance, it our admiration of ourselves. (Paragraph 166)

Darwin’s assertion here that thought is “a secretion of brain” echoes a famous remark by the French physiologist Pierre Jean Georges Cabanis (1757-1808), who wrote in his Rapports du physique et du moral de l’homme (1802) that “to have an accurate idea of the operations from which thought results, it is necessary to consider the brain as a special organ designed especially to produce it, as the stomach and the intestines are designed to operate the digestion, (and) the liver to filter bile…” (English translation, On the Relation Between the Physical and Moral Aspects of Man by Pierre-Jean-George Cabanis, edited by George Mora, translated by Margaret Duggan Saidi from the second edition, reviewed, corrected and enlarged by the author, 1805. The Johns Hopkins University Press, Baltimore and London, 1981, p. 116). This remark is usually cited as the pithy maxim: “The brain secretes thought as the liver secretes bile.

I haven’t finished with Darwin yet. There’s a rather jumbled passage in his Old and Useless Notes about the moral sense & some metaphysical points (1838-1840), in which the young Darwin suggests that consciousness can be explained as the joint product of sensation and memory:

Sensation of higher order where the sensation is conveyed over whole body (which it may be in first case as when the excised heart is pricked) and certain actions (only evidence where not consciousness) are produced in consequence having some relation to the primary sensation – man moving leg when asleep (or habitual actions) – perhaps polypi – (so that lower animals are sleeping higher animals & not plants as supposed by Buffon) Consciousness is sensation No. 2. with memory added to it, man in sleep not conscious, nor child— Evidence of consciousness, movements /?/ anterior to any direct sensation, in order to avoid it – beetles feigning death upon seeing object, – are Planariae conscious. –
(Old & useless notes about the moral sense & some metaphysical points. (1838-1840), Page 9.)

A later passage in the same notebook, written in Darwin’s personal handwriting after a three-page interpolation by another author (possibly Hensleigh Wedgwood), is even more explicit about the possibility of explaining the subjective aspect of consciousness in causal terms:

[We see a particle move one to another, & (or conceive it) & that is all we know of attraction. but we cannot see an atom think: they are as incongruous as blue & weight: all that can be said that thought & organization run in a parallel series, if blueness & weight always went together, & as a thing grew blue it /uniquely/ grew heavier yet it could not be said that the blueness caused the weight, anymore than weight the blueness, still less between action things so different as action thought & organization: But if the weight never came until the blueness had a certain intensity (& the experiment was varied) then might it now be said, that blueness caused weight, because both due to some common cause:- The argument reduced itself to what is cause & effect: it merely is /invariable/ priority of one to other: no not only thus, for if day was first, we should not think night an effect]CD
(Old & useless notes about the moral sense & some metaphysical points. (1838-1840), Page 41 v.)

Here, Darwin displays some hesitation as to the metaphysical question of precisely what makes one event a cause of another. But he is quite confident that once we can isolate the causal antecedents of conscious thought, we have successfully explained it. There’s no doubt about it; Darwin was an out-and-out reductionist.

In their eagerness to divorce the theory of evolution by natural selection from any links to reductionism, Leiter and Weisberg have left us with a watered-down theory that is no longer recognizably Darwinian. One wonders what Charles Darwin would make of it, were he alive today.

(d) Orr: a reductionist materialist account of mind might still be true, even if we’re too stupid to comprehend it

A Big eared townsend bat, (Corynorhinus townsendii). Philosopher Thomas Nagel is the author of a now-famous paper, What is it like to be a bat?, in which he criticized the reductionist program, and argued that current attempts to explain the subjectivity of consciousness in objective terms had failed. Image courtesy of US government and Wikipedia.

In his review of Professor Thomas Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos, biologist Allen Orr concedes that Nagel has made an excellent philosophical case against the possibility of explaining consciousness, which is inherently subjective, in objective scientific terminology, as materialists have attempted to do. However, Orr does not conclude that materialism is false; following philosopher Colin McGinn, he suggests that a materialist account of mind may be true, but that the human mind is too limited to grasp how it would work:

I can’t go so far as to conclude that mind poses some insurmountable barrier to materialism. There are two reasons. The first is, frankly, more a sociological observation than an actual argument. Science has, since the seventeenth century, proved remarkably adept at incorporating initially alien ideas (like electromagnetic fields) into its thinking. Yet most people, apparently including Nagel, find the resulting science sufficiently materialist. The unusual way in which physicists understand the weirdness of quantum mechanics might be especially instructive as a crude template for how the consciousness story could play out. Physicists describe quantum mechanics by writing equations. The fact that no one, including them, can quite intuit the meaning of these equations is often deemed beside the point. The solution is the equation. One can imagine a similar course for consciousness research: the solution is X, whether you can intuit X or not. Indeed the fact that you can’t intuit X might say more about you than it does about consciousness.

And this brings me to the second reason. For there might be perfectly good reasons why you can’t imagine a solution to the problem of consciousness. As the philosopher Colin McGinn has emphasized, your very inability to imagine a solution might reflect your cognitive limitations as an evolved creature. The point is that we have no reason to believe that we, as organisms whose brains are evolved and finite, can fathom the answer to every question that we can ask. All other species have cognitive limitations, why not us? So even if matter does give rise to mind, we might not be able to understand how.

Regarding Professor Orr’s first suggestion, I should point out that the example he offers does not help his case. Quantum mechanics is mysterious, but it is nevertheless capable of being described in mathematical terms. The properties that it describes are thus measurable; they are objective, and can be characterized in third-person terminology. Some versions of quantum theory insist that a conscious observer is needed to collapse the wave-function, but on other accounts, even a measuring device can count as an observer; and in any case, the observations made are publicly shareable. Human and animal consciousness, by contrast, has an ineluctably private and subjective aspect to it, which resists quantification and scientific measurement.

Orr’s second point, that consciousness might be explicable in materialistic terms but that we might not be able to grasp how, is irrefutable on its own terms. But what it overlooks is that in order for Darwinism to be a rationally persuasive account of life, it must appear to us as being capable (at least in principle) of explaining every aspect of life on Earth – including consciousness. If there are sound philosophical reasons showing that human beings will never be able to explain consciousness in Darwinian terms, then we need to confront the question: should the intractability of the problem of consciousness count against Darwin’s theory? Should we reject it for that reason? What Orr is essentially saying is that we shouldn’t: but in so doing, he is implicitly appealing to a “God’s eye” view of Nature. The human mind, he says, is congenitally incapable of grasping itself; but a greater mind than our own (say, that of a Martian) might be able to grasp ours. But of course, it would be unable to grasp its own mind, and would therefore be unable to provide a complete and satisfying account of its own evolution. The same problem besets any other intelligent being within the natural world. Only an eternal, supernatural Deity Whose Mind had never evolved could possibly grasp the “big picture.”

But since Orr does not intend to argue for the existence of God, what he is therefore committed to saying is that we should believe in Darwin’s theory of evolution by natural selection, even though we know that for us, and indeed, for any intelligent life-form, no matter how technologically advanced it may be, any evolutionary account of origins that it comes up with will necessarily be incomplete. If Darwinism is true, then there is one thing about life that a sapient life-form will be forever unable to explain: its own capacity for conscious thought. The irony here is that Charles Darwin himself would have disowned this shocking and somewhat Godelian conclusion. The reason why he put forward his theory of evolution in the first place was in order to provide a complete and overarching explanation of every facet of life.

3. Does the plausibility of Darwinism depend on the origin of life and the emergence of consciousness and intelligence being unsurprising occurrences?

In his book, Mind and Cosmos, Professor Thomas Nagel argues that any adequate explanation of the origins of life, intelligence, and consciousness must show that those events had a significant likelihood of happening, rendering their occurrence unsurprising. He is in good company here: Charles Darwin was of the same view.

(a) Darwin regarded the origin of life as a “not improbable” occurrence

A Gram-negative bacterial flagellum. The base drives the rotation of the hook and filament. Image courtesy of LadyofHats and Wikipedia.

Darwin wisely refused to speculate regarding the exact process by which life had originated: his “warm little pond” example in his letter to Joseph Hooker (February 1st, 1871) was intended purely for the purposes of illustration. Nevertheless, throughout his life, Darwin upheld the view that the origin of life would one day be shown to be an unsurprising occurrence, which could be explained by the simple laws of chemistry.

Writing in his Second Notebook in 1837, twenty-two years before the publication of The Origin of Species, Darwin recorded his serene conviction that “The intimate relation of Life with laws of chemical combination, & the universality of latter render spontaneous generation not improbable.” (Notebook C [Transmutation of species (1838.02-1838.07)], page 102e.) And towards the end of his life, in his February 28, 1882 letter to D. Mackintosh (Letter 13711, Cambridge University Library, DAR.146:335, not yet available online), he wrote that despite the absence of any evidence for a living being developing from inorganic matter, “I cannot avoid believing the possibility of this will be proved some day in accordance with the law of continuity.” (For further references, see Charles Darwin and the Origin of Life by Juli Pereto, Jeffrey L. Bada, and Antonio Lazcano, in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, 2009 October; 39(5): 395-406, doi: 10.1007/s11084-009-9172-7.)

(b) Why Darwin regarded the emergence of consciousness as an unsurprising fact

We have already seen that Darwin referred to thought as “a secretion of brain” in his Notebook C: Transmutation of species (2-7.1838) (paragraph 166), which shows that he was a staunch materialist even as a young man.

On the other hand, Darwin puzzled over the question, “How does consciousness commence,” in his Old and Useless Notes about the moral sense & some metaphysical points (1838-1840, page 35). And in his Descent of Man, published in 1871, Darwin expressed pessimism about the prospects of science being able to identify how consciousness emerged within the foreseeable future:

In what manner the mental powers were first developed in the lowest organisms, is as hopeless an enquiry as how life first originated. These are problems for the distant future, if they are ever to be solved by man.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter 2, page 36.)

At first blush, Darwin’s pessimism regarding the prospects of science belong able to explain how consciousness originated might seem to suggest that he viewed its emergence as a surprising fact. But I would argue that Darwin’s puzzlement about the manner in which consciousness emerged in no way implies that he would have found the fact that it emerged particularly surprising. As the final paragraph of his Origin of Species shows, he was a thoroughgoing materialist, who viewed “the production of the higher animals” as the inevitable outcome of “laws acting around us.”

Moreover, Darwin’s pessimism about solving the historical question of how consciousness emerged did not prevent him from speculating about the “mental powers” of worms a decade later in his 1881 best-seller, The formation of vegetable mould, through the action of worms, with observations on their habits. For Darwin “mental powers” included conscious sensations and feelings, in addition to intelligence. In any case, Darwin was willing to attribute conscious feelings to worms:

Mental Qualities.—There is little to be said on this head. We have seen that worms are timid. It may be doubted whether they suffer as much pain when injured, as they seem to express by their contortions. Judging by their eagerness for certain kinds of food, they must enjoy the pleasure of eating. Their sexual passion is strong enough to overcome for a time their dread of light. They perhaps have a trace of social feeling, for they are not disturbed by crawling over each other’s bodies, and they sometimes lie in contact. According to Hoffmeister they pass the winter either singly or rolled up with others into a ball at the bottom of their burrows.* Although worms are so remarkably deficient in the several sense-organs, this does not necessarily preclude intelligence, as we know from such cases as those of Laura Bridgman; and we have seen that when their attention is engaged, they neglect impressions to which they would otherwise have attended; and attention indicates the presence of a mind of some kind.
(Original edition, 1881, Chapter 1, page 34.)

Evidently Darwin viewed the question of whether worms possess consciousness as scientifically tractable. After reading what Darwin wrote about cause and effect in his remarks on blue and weight in his Old and Useless Notes, it should not be difficult to envisage how a Darwinian research program into the origin of consciousness might proceed. In the conclusion to his book on worms, Darwin went even further, writing that worms “apparently exhibit some degree of intelligence instead of a mere blind instinctive impulse, in their manner of plugging up the mouths of their burrows.”
(Original edition, 1881, Conclusion, page 312.)

Moving further up the “organic scale” (as he called it), Darwin endeavored to persuade his readers that the gradual evolution and refinement of animals’ mental powers over the course of time was a probable occurrence. He began by arguing that consciousness was widely distributed throughout the animal kingdom:

To return to our immediate subject: the lower animals, like man, manifestly feel pleasure and pain, happiness and misery. Happiness is never better exhibited than by young animals, such as puppies, kittens, lambs, &c., when playing together, like our own children. Even insects play together, as has been described by that excellent observer, P. Huber, who saw ants chasing and pretending to bite each other, like so many puppies.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter II, page 39.)

Next, Darwin contended that innumerable grades of consciousness could be found in Nature, linking the lowest and highest animals:

…I shall make some few remarks on the probable steps and means by which the several mental and moral faculties of man have been gradually evolved. That this at least is possible ought not to be denied, when we daily see their development in every infant; and when we may trace a perfect gradation from the mind of an utter idiot, lower than that of the lowest animal, to the mind of a Newton.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter III, page 106)

An ant carrying an aphid. According to Darwin, the difference in mental abilities between an ant and an aphid is much greater than the intellectual difference between a man and an ape. Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

Darwin adduced additional support for his case by arguing that the difference in mental faculties between the highest and lowest animals was one of degree rather than kind, and that the differences in the mental powers of the lower animals were far greater than the differences between the lower and higher animals:

Some naturalists, from being deeply impressed with the mental and spiritual powers of man, have divided the whole organic world into three kingdoms, the Human, the Animal, and the Vegetable, thus giving to man a separate kingdom. (1. Isidore Geoffroy St.-Hilaire gives a detailed account of the position assigned to man by various naturalists in their classifications: ‘Hist. Nat. Gen.’ tom. ii. 1859, pp. 170-189.) Spiritual powers cannot be compared or classed by the naturalist: but he may endeavour to shew, as I have done, that the mental faculties of man and the lower animals do not differ in kind, although immensely in degree. A difference in degree, however great, does not justify us in placing man in a distinct kingdom, as will perhaps be best illustrated by comparing the mental powers of two insects, namely, a coccus or scale-insect and an ant, which undoubtedly belong to the same class. The difference is here greater than, though of a somewhat different kind from, that between man and the highest mammal. The female coccus, whilst young, attaches itself by its proboscis to a plant; sucks the sap, but never moves again; is fertilised and lays eggs; and this is its whole history. On the other hand, to describe the habits and mental powers of worker-ants, would require, as Pierre Huber has shewn, a large volume; I may, however, briefly specify a few points. Ants certainly communicate information to each other, and several unite for the same work, or for games of play. They recognise their fellow-ants after months of absence, and feel sympathy for each other. They build great edifices, keep them clean, close the doors in the evening, and post sentries. They make roads as well as tunnels under rivers, and temporary bridges over them, by clinging together. They collect food for the community, and when an object, too large for entrance, is brought to the nest, they enlarge the door, and afterwards build it up again. They store up seeds, of which they prevent the germination, and which, if damp, are brought up to the surface to dry. They keep aphides and other insects as milch-cows. They go out to battle in regular bands, and freely sacrifice their lives for the common weal. They emigrate according to a preconcerted plan. They capture slaves. They move the eggs of their aphides, as well as their own eggs and cocoons, into warm parts of the nest, in order that they may be quickly hatched; and endless similar facts could be given.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter VI, pp. 186-187.)

There is no evidence from Darwin’s writings that he viewed the evolution of the lower animals, such as worms, as being particularly surprising. Since Darwin was willing to credit worms with consciousness, we may therefore conclude that Darwin did not regard the emergence of consciousness as a surprising or unexpected event. Rather, the evidence suggests that he would have viewed it as the natural outcome of biological laws of variation, acting on simple organisms.

(c) Why Darwin regarded the appearance of human intelligence as an unsurprising fact

Rodin’s Thinker (1902). Musee Rodin, Paris. Image courtesy of Daniel Stockman and Wikipedia.

Darwin was even more sanguine about the prospects for explaining the appearance of human intelligence. In his 1871 work, The Descent of Man, Darwin argued that the emergence of human intelligence was an unsurprising fact, in view of the continuity (as he perceived it) between our mental abilities and those of the “higher animals,” and the survival advantage conferred by intelligence. Darwin maintained that “the difference in mind between man and the higher animals, great as it is, is certainly one of degree and not of kind”
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter III, p. 105), and he charted the steps leading to man in a well-known passage:

In the class of mammals the steps are not difficult to conceive which led from the ancient Monotremata to the ancient Marsupials; and from these to the early progenitors of the placental mammals. We may thus ascend to the Lemuridae and the interval is not wide from these to the Simiadae. The Simiadae then branched off into two great stems, the New World and Old World monkeys; and from the latter, at a remote period, Man, the wonder and glory of the Universe, proceeded.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter VI, p. 213.)

Darwin maintained that because human intelligence conferred a survival advantage on its possessors, the gradual improvement of intelligence in our ape-like ancestors could easily be explained by his theory of evolution by natural selection. Indeed, Darwin advanced this argument in order to rebut the view, put forward by Wallace in an essay in the Quarterly Review of April 1869, that the special intervention of a Higher Intelligence was necessary in order to account for the evolution of human beings from ape-like ancestors:

The case, however, is widely different, as Mr. Wallace has with justice insisted, in relation to the intellectual and moral faculties of man. These faculties are variable; and we have every reason to believe that the variations tend to be inherited. Therefore, if they were formerly of high importance to primeval man and to his ape-like progenitors, they would have been perfected or advanced through natural selection. Of the high importance of the intellectual faculties there can be no doubt, for man mainly owes to them his predominant position in the world. We can see, that in the rudest state of society, the individuals who were the most sagacious, who invented and used the best weapons or traps, and who were best able to defend themselves, would rear the greatest number of offspring. The tribes, which included the largest number of men thus endowed, would increase in number and supplant other tribes.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter V, p. 159.)

Darwin acknowledged that there were certain mental capacities that were unique to human beings, but he minimized the force of this fact by arguing that these abilities originated as by-products of other mental abilities that man shared with the beasts:

We have seen that the senses and intuitions, the various emotions and faculties, such as love, memory, attention, curiosity, imitation, reason, &c., of which man boasts, may be found in an incipient, or even sometimes in a well-developed condition, in the lower animals. They are also capable of some inherited improvement, as we see in the domestic dog compared with the wolf or jackal. If it be maintained that certain powers, such as self-consciousness, abstraction, &c., are peculiar to man, it may well be that these are the incidental results of other highly-advanced intellectual faculties; and these again are mainly the result of the continued use of a highly developed language. At what age does the new-born infant possess the power of abstraction, or become self-conscious and reflect on its own existence? We cannot answer; nor can we answer in regard to the ascending organic scale.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter III, pp. 105-106)

The human capacity for language, however, was not a by-product: for Darwin, it arose by a gradual evolutionary process of progressive modification and refinement of capacities that were already widespread amongst mammals:

“With respect to the origin of articulate language, after having read on the one side the highly interesting works of Mr. Hensleigh Wedgwood, the Rev. F. Farrar, and Prof. Schleicher, and the celebrated lectures of Prof. Max Muller on the other side, I cannot doubt that language owes its origin to the imitation and modification, aided by signs and gestures, of various natural sounds, the voices of other animals, and man’s own instinctive cries.”
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter II, p. 56)

“The half-art and half-instinct of language still bears the stamp of its gradual evolution.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter III, p. 106.)

To sum up: Darwin believed that the origin of life was a scientifically tractable problem which would eventually be explained in terms of the laws of chemistry; that the phenomenon of consciousness could be explained causally in terms of physical sensations and memories, and that his new theory of evolution by natural selection could account for the emergence of human intelligence in a very straightforward manner.

(d) The explanatory merits of Darwinism vs. fairy magic

So I was quite astonished when I read philosopher Elliott Sober chiding Professor Thomas Nagel in his review, for holding views which Darwin himself held: namely, that a successful theory of origins must be able to demonstrate that the origin of life and intelligence were unsurprising events, with a reasonable chance of occurring, over the course of time:

Nagel thinks that adequate explanations of the origins of life, intelligence, and consciousness must show that those events had a “significant likelihood” of occurring: these origins must be shown to be “unsurprising if not inevitable.” A complete account of consciousness must show that consciousness was “something to be expected.” Nagel thinks that evolutionary theory as we now have it fails in this regard, so it needs to be supplemented…

My philosophical feelings diverge from Nagel’s… I don’t think that life, intelligence, and consciousness had to be in the cards from the universe’s beginning. I am happy to leave this question to the scientists. If they tell me that these events were improbable, I do not shake my head and insist that the scientists must be missing something. There is no such must. Something can be both remarkable and improbable.

What Darwin realized, and what Sober appears not to recognize, is that the intellectual appeal of evolution over creationism rests on its being able to account for the history of life on Earth without resorting to ad hoc explanations. Necessarily, any account of the history of life on our planet has to include its beginning, and also the appearance of sentient and sapient life-forms. At the very least, a viable naturalistic theory of origins must demonstrate its ability to account for these events by producing a causally adequate mechanism for the job at hand. But since no physical process has ever been observed to generate life, consciousness or intelligence, the only way to establish the adequacy of a naturalistic theory of origins is to provide a logical argument showing that given enough time, these events were not at all improbable, and that there was some measurable likelihood of their occurrence. Without such an argument, what is the scientific advantage of explaining life in terms of Darwinian evolution, rather than (say) magic?

More than two years ago, I wrote a post on Uncommon Descent, entitled, The 10^(-120) challenge, or: The fairies at the bottom of the garden, in which I challenged neo-Darwinists to provide me with an empirical or mathematical demonstration that the probability of the emergence of life on Earth during the past four billion years as a result of unguided natural processes, starting from a random assortment of organic chemicals, is greater than 10^(-120), or 1 in 1 trillion trillion trillion trillion trillion trillion trillion trillion trillion trillion. As you can see, I set the bar very, very low. No-one from the Darwinist camp took me up on the challenge. I concluded my post on a mocking note, observing that the claim that unguided natural processes (e.g. random mutation and natural selection) produced the first life on Earth is even less scientifically supportable than the fanciful assertion that fairies did the job.

4. Do Nagel’s critics succeed in their attempt to render the origin of life unsurprising?

A game of Scrabble. Many origin-of-life researchers believe that RNA gave rise to both DNA and proteins, but they fail to realize that the appearance of RNA in the first place is astronomically improbable. Professor Dr. Robert Shapiro (1935-2011), who was professor emeritus of chemistry at New York University, has declared: “[S]uppose you took Scrabble sets, or any word game sets, blocks with letters, containing every language on Earth, and you heap them together and you then took a scoop and you scooped into that heap, and you flung it out on the lawn there, and the letters fell into a line which contained the words ‘To be or not to be, that is the question,’ that is roughly the odds of an RNA molecule … appearing on the Earth.” Image courtesy of Wikipedia.

(a) Why the RNA world and the metabolism-first scenario are both fatally flawed explanations for the origin of life

In his review, Professor Elliott Sober argues that even if the evolution of life on Earth should prove to be highly improbable, its appearance at some time and some place in the universe could well be a highly probable occurrence. On this theoretical point, Sober is of course correct; however, he appears to be unaware of recent work by Dr. Douglas Axe, showing that the appearance of even one functional protein, of any kind, was an event so improbable that we would not expect it to happen anywhere in the observable universe, during its 13.7-billion-year history. Dr. Axe has calculated the odds of getting even one functional protein of modest length (150 amino acids) of any kind, by chance, from a pre-biotic soup as less than 1 in 10^164. And in a recent article, The Case Against a Darwinian Origin of Protein Folds (BioComplexity 2010(1):1-12. doi:10.5048/BIO-C.2010.1), Dr. Axe came up with even more daunting odds relating to the likelihood of a new metabolic pathway evolving by chance:

Based on analysis of the genomes of 447 bacterial species, the projected number of different domain structures per species averages 991. Comparing this to the number of pathways by which metabolic processes are carried out, which is around 263 for E. coli, provides a rough figure of three or four new domain folds being needed, on average, for every new metabolic pathway. In order to accomplish this successfully, an evolutionary search would need to be capable of locating sequences that amount to anything from one in 10^159 to one in 10^308 possibilities, something the neo-Darwinian model falls short of by a very wide margin. (p. 11)

The total number of events (or “elementary logical operations”) that could have occurred in the observable universe since the Big Bang has been calculated as no more than 10 to the power of 120 by MIT researcher Seth Lloyd, in his 2002 article, Computational capacity of the universe (Physics Review Leters 88 (2002) 237901, DOI: 10.1103/PhysRevLett.88.237901). So on the best available evidence, the appearance of a protein anywhere in the universe would still be a fantastically improbable event, unless we can point to a non-stochastic process which is more likely to generate proteins than chance alone, or an environment on some other planet that would have been more likely to generate proteins than the primordial Earth. In his ground-breaking book, Signature in the Cell, Dr. Stephen Meyer reviewed non-stochastic processes in detail and concluded that they were unable to account for the specified information we find in proteins, as opposed to the repetitive order we see in polymers.

Indeed, the odds against proteins forming by unguided natural processes are so formidable that many scientists – including biologist H. Allen Orr, who also reviewed Nagel’s book, Mind and Cosmos – now believe that another molecule – RNA – formed first, and that proteins were formed from RNA. In his review, Professor Orr hawks the “RNA world” very persuasively to his readers:

The origin of life is admittedly a hard problem and we don’t know exactly how the first self-replicating system arose. But big progress has been made. The discovery of so-called ribozymes in the 1980s plausibly cracked the main principled problem at the heart of the origin of life. Research on life’s origin had always faced a chicken and egg dilemma: DNA, our hereditary material, can’t replicate without the assistance of proteins, but one can’t get the required proteins unless they’re encoded by DNA. So how could the whole system get off the ground?

Answer: the first genetic material was probably RNA, not DNA. This might sound like a distinction without a difference but it isn’t. The point is that RNA molecules can both act as a hereditary material (as DNA does) and catalyze certain chemical reactions (as some proteins do), possibly including their own replication. (An RNA molecule that can catalyze a reaction is called a ribozyme.) Consequently, many researchers into the origins of life now believe in an “RNA world,” in which early life on earth was RNA-based. “Physical accidents” were likely still required to produce the first RNA molecules, but we can now begin to see how these molecules might then self-replicate.

Orr is a highly qualified biologist, so he must be aware of what Dr. Robert Shapiro (1935-2011), Professor Emeritus of Chemistry at New York University, had to say about the plausibility of the “RNA world” hypothesis. Shapiro realized that the same problem arises for RNA as for proteins: the vast majority of possible sequences are non-functional, and only an astronomically tiny proportion work. In a discussion hosted by Edge magazine in 2008, entitled, Life! What a Concept, with scientists Freeman Dyson, Craig Venter, George Church, Dimitar Sasselov and Seth Lloyd, Shapiro explained why he found the RNA world hypothesis utterly incredible:

…[S]uppose you took Scrabble sets, or any word game sets, blocks with letters, containing every language on Earth, and you heap them together and you then took a scoop and you scooped into that heap, and you flung it out on the lawn there, and the letters fell into a line which contained the words “To be or not to be, that is the question,” that is roughly the odds of an RNA molecule, given no feedback – and there would be no feedback, because it wouldn’t be functional until it attained a certain length and could copy itself – appearing on the Earth.

As is well-known, Professor Shapiro himself favored a “metabolism-first” scenario for the origin of life. However, a recent article entitled, Lack of evolvability in self-sustaining autocatalytic networks: A constraint on the metabolism-first path to the origin of life by Vera Vasasa, Eors Szathmary and Mauro Santos (PNAS January 4, 2010, doi: 10.1073/pnas.0912628107) has highlighted a fundamental problem with the “metabolism-first” scenario: proto-metabolic systems would have been incapable of undergoing Darwinian evolution. In their Abstract, the authors point out that replication of compositional information in the metabolism-first scenario “is so inaccurate that fitter compositional genomes cannot be maintained by selection and, therefore, the system lacks evolvability.” The paper concludes:

We think that the real question is that of the organization of chemical networks. If (and what a big IF) there can be in the same environment distinct, organizationally different, alternative autocatalytic cycles/networks, as imagined for example by Ganti (37) and Wachtershauser (38, 39), then these can also compete with each other and undergo some Darwinian evolution. But, even if such systems exist(-ed), they would in all probability have limited heredity only (cf ref. 34) and thus could not undergo open-ended evolution.

(b) Sober’s “200 probable steps” leading to the appearance of conscious life

At this point, it looks as if Darwin’s modern defenders are down for the count. The origin of life appears to be something of a miracle, and there is no prospect of our being able to explain the emergence of consciousness in terms that we can understand. But Elliott Sober mounts a strong comeback, by proposing an interesting thought experiment in his review of Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos. Briefly, he contends that for all we know, each of the physical steps leading to the first life, and eventually to the appearance of conscious life, may well have been highly probable. In that case, if the emergence of life and consciousness occurred by such a process – and we cannot show that it did not – then it would surely be unreasonable to ask for anything further, by way of an explanation. Even if the eventual outcome (the appearance of conscious life-forms) turns out to be antecedently very unlikely due to the vast number of steps that had to be traversed, the fact that each individual step was highly probable should be enough for us, and no more need be said:

Before leaving the topic of probability, I want to highlight what is involved in Nagel’s requirement that the facts he says are remarkable must be shown to be unsurprising. For the sake of concreteness, let’s take this to mean that the probability must be greater than 1/2. Suppose that to get from the universe’s first moment to the origin of consciousness, 200 stages must be traversed. The universe starts at stage S1, then it needs to pass to S2, then to S3, and so on, until it reaches S200, at which time consciousness makes its first appearance. Suppose further that we have a theory that says that the probability of going from each of these stages to the next is 99/100: this means that each individual step is very likely. Still, the probability of going from S1 all the way to S200 is (99/100)^199, or about 1/10. The demand that the origin of consciousness must have had a probability greater than 1/2 entails that the theory I just described must be wrong or seriously incomplete.

(c) What’s wrong with Sober’s 200 steps: the parable of the tightrope-walker

Photo of Maria Spelterini, walking across a tightrope across the Niagara Gorge, from the United States side to Canada, on 8 July, 1876. Image courtesy of Niagara Falls Public Library and Wikipedia.

I have to say that I find Sober’s reasoning faulty here. To see why, let us imagine a tightrope walker named Letitia, who performs in a circus. Her standard walk is 10 meters long, and her track record indicates that whenever she attempts to walk 10 meters on a tightrope, there is a 99% chance that she will succeed – which is why Letitia never performs her tightrope walk without a safety net. As she is young and has lots of stamina, Letitia’s concentration does not flag over longer distances: thus, over a distance which is N times longer than her standard 10-meter walk, the chance that she will succeed is 0.99^N. We would not consider it too astonishing if Letitia walked along a 100-meter tightrope without falling over; but if she managed to traverse a 2-kilometer tightrope (which is 200 of her standard walks) without falling over, I think most of us would regard that as a somewhat remarkable feat. Still, we might say that she was just lucky; after all, as Sober might point out, the probability that she would succeed was about 1/10 (actually, it’s just under 13.4%). But now let us suppose that the very next day, Letitia manages to complete a 20-kilometer tightrope walk. The odds of this happening by chance are much lower: 0.99^2000, or about 1 in 500 million. At this point, I think most of us would demand an explanation, and we might reasonably suspect that she was cheating: perhaps she was using a fine, invisible wire to help support her. However, when asked about this, Letitia vehemently denies the allegation of cheating, arguing as follows: “There’s nothing surprising about what I did. Sure, I traversed a distance that was equal to 2000 of my standard walks, but the chance that I would complete each stage was 99 in 100. So what’s the big deal?”

We would not be at all impressed by such an argument; and neither should we be by Sober’s example of a 200-stage process leading to the appearance of consciousness. If the origin of life and/or consciousness turns out to be a fantastically improbable event that would not normally be expected to happen even once in the entire history of the universe (as I have argued above), then the fact that each step along the path leading to life and/or consciousness had a 99% chance of being traversed should not lessen our wonderment one little bit. The traversal of the entire path is what needs to be explained, and if the number of steps is large enough, that event will turn out to be astronomically unlikely.

But let us suppose that Letitia continues her protestations of innocence. She pulls out a deck of cards, and deals out several poker hands. “Look,” she says. “Highly improbable events happen all the time. Your poker hand is highly improbable: it’s very unlikely that those particular cards would be dealt. Yet you don’t demand an explanation of that fact. So why do you insist that there must be some explanation of my tightrope-walking feat today? The fact is, there is no explanation. I just got lucky, that’s all. I can’t explain it any more than you can.”

Sober, in his review of Nagel’s book, makes a similar argument, when he points out that some people win the lottery twice, but I would argue that it is a faulty illustration. Double lottery wins do occur; but they are a lot less frequent than single wins, as the laws of probability predict. The same goes for lucky hands. Poker hands obey the laws of probability: very unlikely hands (such as a royal flush) do appear on rare occasions, but more probable hands, such as three of a kind, are much more common. What makes us suspicious of Letitia’s feat is that it is so atypical: an isolated success, very early in her career, with nothing remotely comparable to match it. If she had successfully walked 18, 16 or even 10 kilometers on several previous occasions, we might credit her feat; but if her previous best was 2 kilometers, then we have every right to be skeptical. In short: it is entirely legitimate to look for an alternative explanation of a highly atypical and inherently improbable feat, which renders it more probable than it otherwise would be. And if the feat in question is so improbable that would not normally be expected to happen even once in the history of the universe, then it would be intellectually perverse not to look for an alternative explanation for its occurrence, which rendered it more likely to occur.

The appearance of life can legitimately be described as a feat like Letitia’s tightrope walk, because organisms can do lots of very impressive things: a living cell is an amazing nanoscale factory, whose workings we are still struggling to comprehend. Even a humble protein performs a useful function within a cell; thus the generation of such a protein can also be described as quite a feat. Given the staggering odds against the formation of proteins, let alone living cells or conscious beings, by known natural processes, the quest for an alternative, more probable explanation becomes a scientific imperative.

5. Is a teleological theory of Nature compatible with the scientific method?

Aristotle (384-322 B.C.) proposed a teleological account of science which remained popular in Europe for almost 2,000 years after his death. This bust is a copy of a lost 1st or 2nd century bronze sculpture, made by Lysippos. Image courtesy of the Musee du Louvre, Eric Gaba and Wikipedia.

It is a curious fact that of the three critical reviews I read of Professor Thomas Nagel’s Mind and Cosmos, the one which was most open to the possibility of a genuinely teleological theory of Nature was written by a biologist, while the most decisive rejection of this possibility was penned by a philosopher.

(a) What exactly is Nagel proposing in his teleological theory of Nature?

It needs to be borne in mind that Nagel is an atheist, and that the teleological theory of Nature which he puts forward is an entirely naturalistic one, as Professor H. Allen Orr explains in his review:

While we often associate teleology with a God-like mind – events occur because an agent wills them as means to an end – Nagel finds theism unattractive. But he insists that materialism and theism do not exhaust the possibilities.

Instead he proposes a special species of teleology that he calls natural teleology. Natural teleology doesn’t depend on any agent’s intentions; it’s just the way the world is. There are teleological laws of nature that we don’t yet know about and they bias the unfolding of the universe in certain desirable directions, including the formation of complex organisms and consciousness. The existence of teleological laws means that certain physical outcomes “have a significantly higher probability than is entailed by the laws of physics alone – simply because they are on the path toward a certain outcome.”

Nagel intends natural teleology to be, among other things, a biological theory. It would explain not only the “appearance of physical organisms” but the “development of consciousness and ultimately of reason in those organisms.” Teleology would also provide an “account of the existence of the biological possibilities on which natural selection can operate.”…

One would think, then, that scientists of an atheistic bent, with a philosophical commitment to naturalism, should not find Nagel’s proposals too unsettling. All Nagel is really saying is that it’s a brute fact about Nature that it is biased towards the generation of life and consciousness. Nothing more than that. And yet the ferocity of the Darwinist resistance to even this modest proposal is quite surprising.

(b) Orr’s admission: for all we know, Nature might be teleological

Professor Orr is a biologist whose scientific training is steeped in Darwinism. Despite this fact, I am happy to report that Orr has no objection in principle to Nagel’s teleological views. As he puts it in his review:

I will also be the first to admit that we cannot rule out the formal possibility of teleology in nature. It could turn out that teleological laws affect how the universe unfolds through time. While I suspect some might regard such heterodoxy as a crime against science, Nagel is right that there’s nothing intrinsically unscientific about teleology. If that’s the way nature is, that’s the way it is, and we scientists would need to get on with the business of characterizing these surprising laws. Teleological science is, in fact, more than imaginable. It’s actual, at least historically. Aristotelian science, with its concern for final cause, was thoroughly teleological. And the biological tradition that Darwinism displaced, natural theology, also featured a good deal of teleological thinking.

I believe in giving credit where credit is due, so I would like to thank Orr for opening the door, if ever so slightly, to teleology in the scientific world, even if (as we shall see below), he personally has little time for the notion.

(c) Sober’s rejection of Nagel’s teleological theory of Nature: there can be no teleology without efficient causality

Philosopher Elliott Sober will have none of it, however. His principal objection to Nagel’s proposed scientific program is that in order for teleological facts to be scientific, they have to be explicable not in terms of future states of affairs, but past ones – namely, their causal antecedents. As he puts it in his review:

I do not reject teleology wholesale. I do not reject claims such as “flowers have bright petals because they attract pollinators” and “Sally went to the park at 8:30 because there were fireworks at 9 o’clock.” These statements do not say that a later event caused an earlier one, but they are true because certain causal facts are in place. The statement about flowers is true because there was selection for bright colors among plants that gained from the services of pollinators that used color vision. The statement about fireworks is true because Sally knew there would be fireworks at 9 o’clock, and she wanted to arrive in time to get a good seat. Maybe there are true teleological statements about life, mind, or consciousness. But if there are causal underpinnings for those teleological statements, as there are for the teleological statements about flowers and fireworks, the materialist need not object.

Nagel’s thesis is not just that there are true teleological statements about the emergence of life, mind, and consciousness, but that these statements cannot be explained by a purely causal/materialistic science. Only then does his teleology go beyond what materialistic reductionism allows.

Here, Sober has astutely identified the Achilles’ heel of a naturalistic account of forward-looking teleology: Nature, being unintelligent, does not and cannot look forward. It is precisely for this reason that the Intelligent Design movement contends that the emergence of life and consciousness can only be adequately explained in terms of a Mind which produced them. Nagel, who dislikes theism, does not want to go down this path.

Now, it is one thing to critique the philosophical assumptions underlying Nagel’s teleological account of Nature. It is quite another thing, however, to dogmatically rule out scientific investigation of the claim that some biological changes occurring in Nature are forward-looking, simply because these events “cannot be explained by a purely causal/materialistic science.” If such events occur, then they can and should be scientifically investigated. In that case, it is best that we investigate them as speedily as possible, and move on from there.

6. Are there any good scientific arguments against Nagel’s teleological theory of Nature?

Restoration of Tyrannosaurus rex in a walking posture. Professor H. Allen Orr invokes the extinction of T. rex as a scientific argument against Thomas Nagel’s teleological version of evolution, which says that the universe contains a built-in bias towards the production of sentient and sapient life-forms. Image courtesy of myfavoritedinosaur.com, LadyofHats and Wikipedia.

(a) Why so many non-sentient organisms?

Reading through the reviews of Nagel’s book, I was struck by the weakness of the scientific arguments mounted against Nagel’s teleological theory of Nature. Pulling it apart should have been an easy task for a Darwinist. When I read biologist H. Allen Orr’s review, I expected to encounter substantive criticisms. Instead, what I got was this:

Here’s another problem. Nagel’s teleological biology is heavily human-centric or at least animal-centric. Organisms, it seems, are in the business of secreting sentience, reason, and values. Real biology looks little like this and, from the outset, must face the staggering facts of organismal diversity. There are millions of species of fungi and bacteria and nearly 300,000 species of flowering plants. None of these groups is sentient and each is spectacularly successful. Indeed mindless species outnumber we sentient ones by any sensible measure (biomass, number of individuals, or number of species; there are only about 5,500 species of mammals). More fundamentally, each of these species is every bit as much the end product of evolution as we are. The point is that, if nature has goals, it certainly seems to have many and consciousness would appear to be fairly far down on the list…

The weakness of Orr’s argument should be readily apparent: the fact that most organisms are neither sentient nor sapient should be no more astonishing than the fact that most of the universe is inhospitable to life. What is really astonishing, given the astronomical odds against the formation of life as a result of law-governed causal processes, is that life occurs anywhere in the universe at all. Even its appearance on one planet in the observable universe is a striking and singular fact. The additional fact that our universe gave birth to sentient life is even more startling; and the further fact that sapient life-forms such as human beings emerged is utterly amazing, when one considers the staggering complexity of the human brain (see here for more details). It would be foolish, then, to conclude that consciousness is far down on the list of Nature’s goals, on account of its cosmic rarity, since the other goals accomplished by Nature were far more probable. Putting it poetically, Nagel might say that Nature expended a lot more effort in giving birth to conscious creatures than it did in giving rise to non-sentient bacteria. In assessing Nature’s goals, we should measure not only the proliferation of the targets, but the cost of reaching those targets. Nagel’s point could be made by saying that causally improbable targets come at a very high cost.

I should add that when I say “causal” here, I am of course talking about what Aristotle would call efficient causes, rather than final causes. It is a sad deficiency of the modern scientific worldview, that the latter are erroneously thought to be reducible to the former – a conclusion that Aristotle would have laughed at, as he insisted in his Physics Book 2 part 8 that “action for an end is present in things which come to be and are by nature”: in other words, efficient causality presupposed final causality, rather than the other way round. In modern jargon: in order for a thing to act and produce an effect in the first place [efficient causality], it needs to already have built-in tendencies or causal dispositions to generate this effect [final causality].

(b) Why so many extinctions?

Professor Orr also argues that extinction renders Thomas Nagel’s teleological account of Nature unlikely:

Nagel’s astonishment that a “sequence of viable genetic mutations” has been available to evolution over billions of years is also unfounded. His concern appears to be that evolution requires an unbroken chain of viable genetic variants that connect the first living creature to, say, human beings. How could nature ensure that a viable mutation was always available to evolution? The answer is that it didn’t. That’s why species go extinct. Indeed that’s what extinction is. The world changes and a species can’t find a mutation fast enough to let it live. Extinction is the norm in evolution: the vast majority of all species have gone extinct. Nagel has, I think, been led astray by a big survivorship bias: the evolutionary lineage that led to us always found a viable mutation, ergo one must, it seems, always be available. Tyrannosaurus rex would presumably be less impressed by nature’s munificence.

Once again, it seems to me that Orr is missing the point that Professor Nagel is trying to make, which is that it is a non-trivial and highly remarkable fact that there is a “sequence of viable genetic mutations” leading to conscious life. We can easily imagine a planet harboring life, where there was no such sequence, and where nothing more advanced than bacteria could ever evolve. Nagel’s legitimate puzzlement at the existence of a pathway leading to sentient and sapient beings cannot be airbrushed away: it requires an explanation.

And while we’re on the subject of extinction, let’s remember that mammals (most of whom are presumably sentient) have been on this Earth for 200 million years. During that time, Tyrannosaurus rex has come and gone; mammals are still here.

Furthermore, there are extinctions and extinctions. Homo erectus (who is presumably our ancestor) is now extinct; but before he went extinct, some of his descendants evolved into Homo heidelbergensis, the ancestor of Homo sapiens. Tyrannosaurus rex, on the other hand, left no descendants.

This last consideration suggests a possible test for Nagel’s theory. If the universe contains a built-in bias towards sentient life, then the rate of extinctions on the evolutionary pathway leading to sentient organisms should be lower than the rate of extinctions on the paths leading to non-sentient organisms. This would be an interesting avenue to pursue.

7. Could consciousness be a byproduct?

In his review, Professor Elliott Sober charges Thomas Nagel with inconsistency in accepting that many evolutionary outcomes (e.g. the fact that our blood is red) can be byproducts, while making a special exception for consciousness:

Not only does Nagel require that remarkable facts be fairly probable; he also insists that they can’t be byproducts (a.k.a. side effects). He applies this requirement to the appearance of minds, consciousness, and reasoning. Nagel doesn’t reject all byproduct explanations. For example, he is comfortable with the standard evolutionary account of why vertebrate blood is red. This didn’t happen because there was an adaptive advantage in having red blood. Rather, the hemoglobin molecule was selected because it transports oxygen to tissues, and hemoglobin just happens to make our blood red…

Evolutionary biology leaves open the possibility that even Nagel’s remarkable facts are byproducts. For instance, the co-discoverers of the theory of evolution by natural selection, Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace, disagreed about how the human capacity for abstract theoretical reasoning should be explained. Darwin saw it as a byproduct. There was selection for reasoning well in situations that made a difference for survival and reproduction, and our capacity to reason about mathematics and natural science and philosophy is a happy byproduct. Wallace, on the other hand, thought that a spiritualistic explanation was needed. Nagel finds Darwin’s side effect account “very far-fetched,” but he does not say why.

I would like to reply, first of all, by pointing out that “by-product” explanations are inherently reductive, whereas the whole point of Professor Nagel’s book is that a reductionist account of life and consciousness is impossible in principle. For instance, consciousness cannot be a spin-off of something else: there is literally nothing for it to spin off from, for if there were, it would have to be either subjective (in which case it would already be conscious) or objective (in which case it could never explain consciousness, on Nagel’s view).

I would also like to add that Charles Darwin himself did not view the emergence of either consciousness or intelligence as a spin-off: as we saw above, he ascribed both, in a rudimentary form, even to humble worms, and he also believed that every possible gradation of mental powers between the highest and lowest animals could be found in Nature, leaving no unbridgeable gaps. The only mental capacities that he regarded as spin-offs were those unique to man, and he explained these in terms of “other highly-advanced intellectual faculties”:

If it be maintained that certain powers, such as self-consciousness, abstraction, &c., are peculiar to man, it may well be that these are the incidental results of other highly-advanced intellectual faculties.
(The Descent of Man, 1st edition, 1871, Chapter III, p. 105.)

Finally, I’ll say more in Part 9 (below) about why our capacity to reason about mathematics and natural science cannot be grounded in abilities that “made a difference for survival and reproduction.” The short answer is that science is not about survival, or even success: it is about truth. A successful hypothesis may or may not be a true one, as many different hypotheses – perhaps infinitely many – may turn out to be capable of explaining the same set of facts.

8. Faced with a choice between evolution and objective morality, which should we choose?

Auschwitz II – Birkenau – Entrance gate and main track. About one million Jews were killed at this concentration camp. The Holocaust of the Jews is often cited as an example of an example of objective moral evil. Image courtesy of C.Puisney and Wikipedia.

(a) Sober: If there is an objective moral code, does it need to explain why we believe in that code?

The question, “Faced with a choice between evolution and objective morality, which should we choose?” might seem like a no-brainer. If we want to stay human, we’ll hang on to our objective morality. A community which declares that morality is merely a social construct debases itself. It also lays itself open to the possibility of anti-social individuals saying: “I don’t want to play that game. I’m going to change the rules.” What happens to morality then?

But do we need to make such a choice? Professor Nagel thinks we do. Philosopher Elliott Sober handily summarizes Nagel’s argument in his review:

Nagel’s idea is that if you don’t need to postulate the existence of moral facts to explain why we have the moral beliefs we have, then you should slice those alleged facts away. This doesn’t just mean that you should decline to believe that there are moral facts of the sort that moral realism postulates. It means that you should believe that there are no such things… [Ockham’s] razor doesn’t tell you to suspend judgment; it tells you to deny. That is Nagel’s reason for thinking that there is a conflict between evolutionary theory and moral realism: evolutionary theory underwrites a parsimony argument against moral realism.

Sober comments:

I don’t buy this argument. I agree that you don’t need to postulate moral truths to have an evolutionary explanation for why we have the moral beliefs we do. But that doesn’t mean that evolutionary theory justifies denying that there are such truths. Nagel is assuming that if moral realism is true, then the truth of moral propositions must be part of the explanation for why we believe those propositions. I disagree; the point of ethics is to guide our behavior, not to explain it, a thesis that Nagel defended in The View from Nowhere (1989) but has now apparently abandoned.

I am afraid that Sober’s argument would only work in a society of people who never questioned the basis for their moral norms. To illustrate this point, let us imagine a Paleolithic tribe of people who obey moral norms, but who haven’t yet succeeded in reasoning their way to the existence of objective moral norms. One fine day, a bright young individual pipes up and says: “Why are we blindly obeying these norms? After all, these norms are for us, aren’t they? Why can’t we change them, if we want to? Come to think of it, why can’t I change them, if I want to?” At this point, someone in the tribe had better come up with the idea that morality is objective, or there will be mayhem, and perhaps murder as well. Once this moral “critical point” is reached (and it must have been reached at a fairly early stage in human history), it becomes essential, for the sake of social stability, that the objective truth of the moral code explains why people believe the propositions contained in that code.

(b) Leiter and Weisberg: If evolution and objective morality conflict, maybe we should jettison objective morality

The reaction of Leiter and Weisberg to Nagel’s argument is even more remarkable. The authors demonstrate real chutzpah when they calmly assert that Nagel’s belief in an objective morality runs contrary to common sense:

To begin, there is nothing remotely common-sensical about Nagel’s confidence in the objectivity of moral truth. While Nagel and his compatriots apparently take very seriously their moral opinions – so seriously that they find it incredible to suggest that their “confidence in the objective truth of [their] moral beliefs” might, in fact, be “completely illusory” – this can hardly claim the mantle of “the common sense view.” Ordinary opinion sometimes tends toward objectivism, to be sure – often by relying on religious assumptions that Nagel explicitly rejects – but it also often veers toward social or cultural relativism about morality. Whether morality is truly objective is a philosopher’s claim (and a controversial one even among philosophers) about which “common sense” is either agnostic or mixed.

This, I have to say, is utterly ridiculous. Ask any group of ordinary people whether the Holocaust was objectively wrong, and I’m pretty sure I know what answer you’ll get. If you ask most of those people whether torturing animals for fun is objectively wrong, I’m sure they’d still say yes. Ask them whether adultery is objectively wrong, and most of them (atheists included) would still be inclined to agree. Ditto for malicious gossip. On questions relating to lying and stealing, you’ll probably encounter some case-by-case reasoning. Does this indicate that people are moral relativists? Not at all. Casuistry and moral objectivity are by no means mutually contradictory. All that the use of casuistry shows is that morality isn’t always simple.

It is on the topic of sexual mores, however, that you are likely to see the most prevarication, if you quiz people about their opinions. But even here, it is worth noting that few people are pure moral subjectivists. Hardly anybody really believes that “anything goes” with regard to sex. The same people who advocate tolerance of alternative lifestyles have developed their own new set of moral prohibitions: the idea that people might voluntarily enter into an arranged marriage, even though they do not yet love each other, is regarded with utter horror; consensual marriages between people of markedly different ages are now heavily frowned upon; sexual infidelity is now deemed acceptable for liberated couples, but emotional infidelity is viewed as an unforgivable sin; women who choose to have four or more children, or to become full-time home-makers, are regarded as poor deluded prisoners of patriarchy who must be “enlightened”; and finally, there is an increasing number of “educators” (I won’t call them teachers) who believe that even kindergarten children have the inalienable right to learn about all manner of sexual practices and the lifestyles that go with them – and that anyone (parents included) who tells a young child that some of these practices are morally wrong is guilty of child abuse! In short: one set of moral absolutes has replaced another.

But Professor Leiter and Weisberg are not finished yet, on the subject of morality. In a short paragraph, they provide a splendid illustration of the adage that one person’s modus ponens is another person’s modus tollens. They hint that if evolution and objective morality conflict, maybe we should jettison objective morality:

We take no stance on Nagel’s hypothesis that if our moral faculties are simply the result of evolution, they cannot be reliable measures of objective moral truth. But we should note that Nagel’s colleague, philosopher Sharon Street, accepts it and draws the opposite conclusion. She argues that because this hypothesis is true, and because we are obviously the products of evolution, we should give up the idea that there are objective moral truths in Nagel’s sense.

Has it really come to this? Have we sunk this low? Is it really rational to be more certain of the truth of evolution than of the existence of objective moral truths, such as the fact that killing people for sport is wrong? Of course not. Sharon Street has forgotten that the entire case for Darwinian evolution rests upon nothing more than converging lines of circumstantial evidence. Even if we grant – and I don’t – that the various lines of scientific evidence do converge on Darwinism, that evidence is still circumstantial, rendering the conclusion highly probable, rather than certain. By contrast, the rational intuition that killing people for sport is wrong is direct, immediate and (for any person with a properly formed sense of morality) as indubitable as the proposition that 2 + 2 = 4. And the fact that philosophers do not currently agree about what a rational intuition is (Socratic fallacy, anyone?) or precisely why we should trust our rational intuition that killing people for sport is wrong, should no more weaken our conviction that this intuition is true, than the fact that philosophers continue to disagree about the epistemic foundations of mathematical knowledge should weaken our conviction that the proposition, “2 + 2 = 4” is true.

9. Neurath’s boat: does evolutionary naturalism undermine the validity of scientific reasoning?

A group of people riding a wooden boat off a beach in Venezuela. The philosopher Otto Neurath used the metaphor of a leaky boat that is continually being repaired by its crew to describe the way in which we continually revise our beliefs. As W. V. O. Quine expressed it in Word and Object: “We are like sailors who on the open sea must reconstruct their ship but are never able to start afresh from the bottom. Where a beam is taken away a new one must at once be put there, and for this the rest of the ship is used as support. In this way, by using the old beams and driftwood the ship can be shaped entirely anew, but only by gradual reconstruction.” Image courtesy of Rufino Uribe and Wikipedia.

Finally, Professor Nagel argues in his book that neo-Darwinian evolution also undermines our confidence in theoretical reasoning, especially when it relates to the “Big Questions” of where we came from, what we are and where we’re going:

Any evolutionary account of the place of reason presupposes reason’s validity and cannot confirm it without circularity.

Eventually the attempt to understand oneself in evolutionary, naturalistic terms must bottom out in something that is grasped as valid in itself – something without which the evolutionary understanding would not be possible.

In their reply to Nagel’s argument, Professors Leiter and Weisberg offer their readers an old parable about a leaky boat:

There is a response to this kind of challenge, one that is widely embraced by philosophical naturalists (though, again, not mentioned by Nagel). This response starts by noting that we determine what is “rational” or “justified” simply by appealing to the most successful forms of inquiry into the world that human beings have developed…

Philosophical naturalists often appeal to the metaphor of “Neurath’s Boat,” named after the philosopher who developed it. Our situation as inquirers trying to understand the world around us, according to Neurath, is like that of sailors who must rebuild their ship while at sea. These sailors do not have the option of abandoning the ship and rebuilding a new one from scratch. They must, instead, try to rebuild it piecemeal, all the time staying afloat on other parts of the ship on which they continue to depend. In epistemological terms, we are also “at sea”: we cannot abandon all the knowledge about the world we have acquired from the sciences and then ask what we really know or what is really rational. The sciences that have worked so well for us are precisely our benchmark for what we know and what is rational; they’re the things that are keeping us “afloat.” Extending this metaphor, we can say that Nagel is the sailor who says, “I know the ideal form a ship should take – it is intuitively obvious, I am confident in it – so let us jump into the ocean and start building it from scratch.”

I have to say that I regard this as an unsatisfactory response. Briefly: the fact that a scientific hypothesis is successful in accounting for our observations doesn’t make it true in any objective sense: there are a potentially infinite number of alternative hypotheses that could explain the same facts, and the fact that we haven’t stumbled on them all merely indicates a lack of imagination on our part. Professor Nagel is therefore entirely within his rights in asking how we could know whether Darwin’s theory of evolution is true, if we accept an evolutionary account of reason. Even if the theory were successful in accounting for the known biological facts (and it certainly isn’t, as my preceding remarks about abiogenesis show, not to mention the origin of animal body plans), that alone wouldn’t make it true or even probable; it would merely make it preferable to creationism.

So what would guarantee that our scientific hypotheses actually track the truth? As far as I can tell, only one thing: a God Who created our minds with a built-in bias towards a set of explanatory metaphors (or models) that actually reflected the way things really are. Perhaps such a God might implant these metaphors in our minds; alternatively, He could design a world that was “stocked” with a sufficient number of highly visible everyday objects instantiating all of the right metaphors required for scientists to understand the cosmos, thereby guaranteeing that they would rely on these objects when forming scientific explanations, and eventually hit upon the right explanation of the world around them. I can’t see any other way that science would track the truth, even roughly, over the course of time. Nagel won’t want to follow me here, of course, since he is an atheistic naturalist. But I would like to finish my review by thanking Professor Nagel for asking all the right questions. That’s a very good start.

Comments
KN:
That would depend on what Kant was wrong about.
How about his epistemology? Since it's not unreasonable to think his other ideas were derived from his theory of knowledge, it could be a real problem if he got that wrong. :)Mung
February 12, 2013
February
02
Feb
12
12
2013
10:29 AM
10
10
29
AM
PDT
KN @ 60:
The first is to work out some ideas of my own in dialogue with others. I firmly believe that our theories are best developed by exposing them to the harshest criticism. Since Uncommon Descent is a hotbed of anti-naturalism, I figure it’s a good place to see how well my version of naturalism fares by comparison.
For what purpose? The only purpose I see in what you've written here is that philosphy, to you, is like a game of chess. You want to see how your lexicon and tactics fare against that of others, but refuse to say that it ultimately serves any purpose, because you don't even suggest that others should adopt your philosophy for any reason. IOW, if your philosphy "fares well" in your opinion, so what? What does that accomplish for you other than a sense of satisfaction and pride in your philosophical construct?
The second is to indicate to the anti-naturalists that there are intellectually respectable alternatives to the views that they have embraced, and hopefully to make them more aware of the space of possibilities, to enlarge their philosophical imaginations, and to be somewhat less dogmatic in their fundamental commitments.
Why should they be made so aware, and why should they be less dogmatic in their fundamental commitments?
As for what I take the task of philosophy to be, and what it is that I am aiming for, I can do no better than quote Sellars:
I don't understand what he/she is trying to say in that quote. Could you paraphrase it for me?William J Murray
February 12, 2013
February
02
Feb
12
12
2013
08:16 AM
8
08
16
AM
PDT
And if Kant was wrong?
That would depend on what Kant was wrong about. I think he was clearly wrong about some things, and clearly right about some others, and on most points I suspect he's on the right track. It would take a lot of convincing to persuade me that he's completely wrong about everything.Kantian Naturalist
February 12, 2013
February
02
Feb
12
12
2013
07:18 AM
7
07
18
AM
PDT
I comment here for two reasons. The first is to work out some ideas of my own in dialogue with others. I firmly believe that our theories are best developed by exposing them to the harshest criticism. Since Uncommon Descent is a hotbed of anti-naturalism, I figure it's a good place to see how well my version of naturalism fares by comparison. The second is to indicate to the anti-naturalists that there are intellectually respectable alternatives to the views that they have embraced, and hopefully to make them more aware of the space of possibilities, to enlarge their philosophical imaginations, and to be somewhat less dogmatic in their fundamental commitments. As for what I take the task of philosophy to be, and what it is that I am aiming for, I can do no better than quote Sellars:
The aim of philosophy, abstractly formulated, is to understand how things in the broadest possible sense of the term hang together in the broadest possible sense of the term. Under 'things in the broadest possible sense' I include such radically different items as not only 'cabbages and kings', but numbers and duties, possibilities and finger snaps, aesthetic experience and death. To achieve success in philosophy would be, to use a contemporary turn of phrase, to 'know one's way around' with respect to all these things, not in that unreflective way in which the centipede of the story knew its way around before it faced the question, 'how do I walk?', but in that reflective way which means that no intellectual holds are barred. (from "Philosophy and the Scientific Image of Man)"
Kantian Naturalist
February 12, 2013
February
02
Feb
12
12
2013
07:15 AM
7
07
15
AM
PDT
KN:
But Kant is the source from which those disparate rivers flow.
And if Kant was wrong?Mung
February 11, 2013
February
02
Feb
11
11
2013
02:49 PM
2
02
49
PM
PDT
KN says:
I do, of course, regard my view as eminently plausible, helpful, more right than not, etc
1, More plausible according to what arbitrating metric? 2. More helpful to whom, and in what way? 3. More "right" according to what ethical or moral system? Or do you mean "correct"? If so, more correct in comparison to what presumed standard?
I wouldn’t presume to say ... that other people ought to share it.
4. Then why are you arguing it here, and using it to argue against other views?William J Murray
February 11, 2013
February
02
Feb
11
11
2013
02:39 PM
2
02
39
PM
PDT
I do, of course, regard my view as eminently plausible, helpful, more right than not, etc. I wouldn't presume to say that my view is absolutely correct, or that other people ought to share it. The reason why I put "Kantian" in my pseudonym isn't because I share his transcendental idealism (and what follows from it) -- on the contrary, I am a metaphysical realist -- but because of other commitments he has which I think are of the utmost importance and which are separable from the idealism within which he develops them. If I had to specify my philosophical lineage more precisely, I would say that I have three main lines of influence: the pragmatism that runs from Peirce through Dewey and C. I. Lewis to Sellars and Brandom; the phenomenology that runs from Husserl through Sartre and Heidegger to Merleau-Ponty; and the critical theory that runs from Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, and Freud through the Frankfurt School to Habermas. But Kant is the source from which those disparate rivers flow.Kantian Naturalist
February 11, 2013
February
02
Feb
11
11
2013
12:50 PM
12
12
50
PM
PDT
WJM:
What’s the job?
Only KN can say, but if I had to guess, the "job" is to somehow find intellectual fulfillment while not allowing a divine foot in the door. I suppose one must imagine Sisyphus happy.Phinehas
February 10, 2013
February
02
Feb
10
10
2013
07:38 PM
7
07
38
PM
PDT
Phinehas said:
But for you, it evidently does the job.
What's the job? As far as I have been able to discern, KN doesn't assert that his philosophy serves any useful or meaningful purpose other than - apparently - self-gratifying iconoclasm. What's the point in arguing for a philosophy unless one holds that the philosophy is true, and/or that it better serves a significant, necessary purpose that others should also be working towards?William J Murray
February 9, 2013
February
02
Feb
9
09
2013
02:25 AM
2
02
25
AM
PDT
KN: I find your philosophy fascinating much in the same way I find a Rube Goldberg machine fascinating. It appears so detailed and intricate and borrows from so many disparate concepts that I have difficulty following its wends and ways and wonder how it can work at all. But for you, it evidently does the job. Do you ever feel like you are searching for philosophical medications to address the side-effects of other philosophical medications, which in turn were essential to address the side-effects of...?Phinehas
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
03:25 PM
3
03
25
PM
PDT
Kantian Naturalist (49): Kant was no naturalist.
At least Immanuel got that right ...Box
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
02:27 PM
2
02
27
PM
PDT
KN: Pardon, but first, there is indeed a patent bit of self-referential incoherence involved. SB has further outlined it. Next, at no point have I globally endorsed Royce [I am after all a Protestant!], just acknowledged him as making an apt point, thereby paying my intellectual debt. Indeed, one first drawn to my attention by Trueblood. KFkairosfocus
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
02:11 PM
2
02
11
PM
PDT
kairosfocus
Namely, that it is making a self referential major knowledge claim that knowledge of the relevant class is impossible?
Kantian Naturalist
There are some fatally serious errors in Kant’s philosophy, but I don’t think that’s one of them.
One must know something about reality in order to say that we cannot know anything about reality. That follows as surely as night follows day. To say, then, that we cannot know anything about reality, is to make a self-refuting statement.
Briefly put, Kant claims that there are anthropogenic epistemic conditions: conditions on what must be the case in order for there to be any knowledge at all, and those conditions lie in our cognitive constitution.
That is just another way of saying that we cannot know anything about reality. The attempt to justify the claim does not render it any less incoherent.
Now, if all knowledge presupposes that the epistemic conditions are satisfied, and if the relevant epistemic conditions are anthropogenic — they lie in how the human mind is organized or constituted — then it follows that we cannot know how things are independently of the satisfaction of those conditions, and hence we cannot how it is with things in themselves.
That Kant's conclusion is self-contradictory indicates that the reasoning behind it is invalid.
The existence of error is no objection to Kant; nor does Kant reject the correspondence theory of truth, although there is a mighty slippery slope from Kant to coherentism about truth.
As Kant often does, he tries to have it both ways. On the one hand, he acknowledges correspondence theory in so many words. On the other hand, he re-defines it as the mind in correspondence with itself by subjectivizing the object, which is really just another way of denying correspondence theory. :"(...) Truth, it is said, consists in the agreement of cognition with its object. In consequence of this mere nominal definition, my cognition, to count as true, is supposed to agree with its object. Now I can compare the object with my cognition, however, only by cognizing it. Hence my cognition is supposed to confirm itself, which is far short of being sufficient for truth. For since the object is outside me, the cognition in me, all I can ever pass judgement on is whether my cognition of the object agrees with my cognition of the object. The ancients called such a circle in explanation a diallelon. And actually the logicians were always reproached with this mistake by the sceptics, who observed that with this definition of truth it is just as when someone makes a statement before a court and in doing so appeals to a witness with whom no one is acquainted, but who wants to establish his credibility by maintaining that the one who called him as witness is an honest man. The accusation was grounded, too. Only the solution of the indicated problem is impossible without qualification and for every man. (...)"StephenB
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
01:49 PM
1
01
49
PM
PDT
OT: kf, you may appreciate this video lecture by Dr. Tim McGrew. The video is the only lecture of his where I've actually seen what he looks like, usually the lectures just have slides with no view of Dr. McGrew personally. Who Wrote the Gospels? - Dr. Timothy McGrew - video https://vimeo.com/57485839bornagain77
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
01:42 PM
1
01
42
PM
PDT
Firstly, the claim that Kant's claim is self-undermining, of the sort, "we know that we cannot know", rests on a misreading of the argument. I thought I'd pointed out that out. Secondly, the existence of error is no objection to Kant's epistemology. (How it could it, when Royce himself is an absolute idealist, or as he called his view, "absolute pragmatism"?) Thirdly, this raises an important point:
Knowing how the human mind is constituted etc etc all fall within the issue at the pivot of my concern. Yes, I am perfectly willing to accept that our knowledge of the world is conditioned by our constitution and even filtered/”coloured” by it and distorted by it in some cases — not to mention sometimes outright erroneous, but the moment one reaches that one step too far and generalises, nope.
Of course there are certain kinds of "colourations", so to speak, which are detectable and avoidable -- we can use more powerful telescopes or microscopes, we can do double-blind studies to control for biases, etc. -- but that's not the kind of anthropogenic epistemic conditions that Kant worries about. So maybe I should say a bit more about this. Kant's most basic concern is: what must a being be like in order to be able to judge, to form judgments and to assess them? In particular, what must a being be like in order to have empirical judgments, i.e. to make assertions about what it experiences? The judgments must have both a form and a content. The form is a priori, just because we couldn't have any experiences of objects at all if there wasn't some kind of basic cognitive structure up and running to begin with. The a priori form of judgment has two distinct sources: (i) concepts, which are rules for judging, and (ii) intuitions, which pick out individual objects to be judged. The a priori concepts are what Kant calls "categories of the understanding," and he famously claims that there are only twelve of them. (Needless to say, no one today follows Kant on that specific point!). The a priori form of intuition is what in what Kant calls "the forms of intuition", or what might be better called pure sensible intuition. (Kant suggests, and I think rightly, that the concept of pure sensible intuition is the very heart of his breakthrough with both rationalism and empiricism. The rationalists held that we have intellectual intuition as well as sensible intuition; the empiricists held that we have only empirical intuition. The thought that there could be sensible intuition that was not empirical -- a kind of representation that was neither a concept nor a sensation -- is central to everything else Kant does.) Famously, Kant claims that there two forms of intuition: space and time. Now, one might be willing to entertain this much but yet balk at Kant's next move, which is that space and time exist only for us. It's a very radical subjectivization of space and time, and as a result, the only thing that preserves the objectivity of empirical judgments is that all human minds are organized along the same basic lines. So objectivity cashes out as intersubjectivity, and for many philosophers, that's just not good enough. That said, there are also lots of philosophers who think that what is really important in Kant's philosophy can be separated from his own commitment to transcendental idealism, and I'm one of them. Hence the "naturalism" in my screen-name. Kant was no naturalist.Kantian Naturalist
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
11:57 AM
11
11
57
AM
PDT
KN: Pardon, but you are speaking with someone raised on proof by contradiction of alternative assertion. (And yes, I know there are those who dispute such proofs.) When a system ends up in a howler like asserting a self referential claim that undermines itself, that is enough for me, and it points a dagger at the heart of the system that threw it out. Knowing how the human mind is constituted etc etc all fall within the issue at the pivot of my concern. Yes, I am perfectly willing to accept that our knowledge of the world is conditioned by our constitution and even filtered/"coloured" by it and distorted by it in some cases -- not to mention sometimes outright erroneous, but the moment one reaches that one step too far and generalises, nope. An excellent counter instance is exactly the undeniable certainty of our knowledge that error exists. KFkairosfocus
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
11:29 AM
11
11
29
AM
PDT
In re: Kairosfocus @ 46: There are some fatally serious errors in Kant's philosophy, but I don't think that's one of them. On the contrary, it's a direct entailment of his transcendental idealism. Briefly put, Kant claims that there are anthropogenic epistemic conditions: conditions on what must be the case in order for there to be any knowledge at all, and those conditions lie in our cognitive constitution. His argument for why there must be anthropogenic epistemic conditions long and complicated, but his key move is what's called his "Copernican Revolution": if the epistemic conditions are anthropogenic, then we can eliminate all cases of "reason's conflict with itself" (free will vs. determinism, naturalism vs. theism, etc.). (I won't get into the details as to what the anthropogenic epistemic conditions are.) Now, if all knowledge presupposes that the epistemic conditions are satisfied, and if the relevant epistemic conditions are anthropogenic -- they lie in how the human mind is organized or constituted -- then it follows that we cannot know how things are independently of the satisfaction of those conditions, and hence we cannot how it is with things in themselves. The existence of error is no objection to Kant; nor does Kant reject the correspondence theory of truth, although there is a mighty slippery slope from Kant to coherentism about truth.Kantian Naturalist
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
09:34 AM
9
09
34
AM
PDT
KN: Don't you see the problem with:
Kant holds that we cannot know how reality in itself really is, we can only know reality as it appears to us.
Namely, that it is making a self referential major knowledge claim that knowledge of the relevant class is impossible? As in self-undermining? I would think that instead error exists, per Josiah Royce and Elton Trueblood is a more promising start. For this is conceded by all and is seen to be undeniable. Thus it is a knowable and certain truth, humbling though it be. KFkairosfocus
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
08:08 AM
8
08
08
AM
PDT
Alan Fox wrote: "the ID movement is gently drifting into cod philosophy and obscurity and I’m giving my scepticism a rest as I think ID is managing to decline very nicely without my input." I don't know what "cod philosophy" is, but the charge sounds fishy to me. :-) As for decline, I think the opposite. Every day the biologists and biochemists discover new intricacies, new layers of control in the DNA-protein system, new overlapping and integrated systems, new complex interplay between genomic and developmental factors. Each new discovery is a nail in the coffin of neo-Darwinism, which says that all these *tightly integrated* features of life arose one random mutation at a time, as life stumbled blindly through killing defects and "improvements" that couldn't improve anything until a score of other things improved in co-ordination with them. Already biologists are partnering with engineers, computer programmers, information theorists, etc. to understand living systems -- because the realistic biologists understand, instinctively, even if they can't yet bring themselves to use the word, that these systems can't be understood without the notion of design. It's only the ideological biologists, the ones still living in 19th-century materialism, that think we can have a design-free biology. And anyway, it's not in the biologists' power to stop these developments, even if they wanted to. Nothing can stop a sharp physicist, engineer, or computer scientist from learning some basic biology, and then treating living systems as designed systems, and publishing his results in *physics* or *engineering* or *information theory* journals. And since those fields have their *own* criteria of "good science," and their own systems of hiring, promotion, and research grants, the old-style biologists, with their 1940s population genetics, can squawk all they want, cursing the new developments in the name of the ghosts of Mayr and Dobzhansky, but they can't stop scientific careers being built in a new evolutionary biology which is increasingly being studied in departments other than biology. The future is with life scientists who think like physicists, engineers, and mathematicians, not like laissez-faire economists. And that's all neo-Darwinism ever was, laissez-faire economics translated into the idiom of population genetics. It's moribund science, and those who hang onto it will be a laughingstock 10 or 20 years from now. As Thomas Kuhn would say, the paradigm in evolutionary biology is shifting, from an economics model to an engineering/physics/information theory model, and this shift can no more be stopped than the shift from alchemy to modern chemistry could be stopped. This is why it is such a joke that the venom directed at ID for being "bad science" comes mainly from neo-Darwinists. They are precisely the ones who are going to be regarded as the equivalent of alchemists and astrologers as 21st-century biology proceeds. Alan, you are backing the losing horse.Timaeus
February 8, 2013
February
02
Feb
8
08
2013
04:37 AM
4
04
37
AM
PDT
Do you swear to tell the truth, the whole truth, and nothing but the truth, so help you God? Ummm... I'm Bohr'd.Mung
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
06:13 PM
6
06
13
PM
PDT
Axel, In saying that "Bohr was a good Kantian," what I meant is th following. Kant holds that we cannot know how reality in itself really is, we can only know reality as it appears to us. And how we describe reality-as-it-appears depends on the conceptual framework that we have. Bohr applies this notion in his principle of complementarity: we can describe quantum phenomena as if they are waves, and we can describe them as if they are particles, and both descriptions yield useful and valuable knowledge of the phenomena, but neither description captures the whole truth of the phenomena, and indeed the whole truth of the phenomena is not accessible to us.Kantian Naturalist
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
05:56 PM
5
05
56
PM
PDT
For the sake of concreteness, let’s take this to mean that the probability must be greater than 1/2.
haha. not quite on a par with the level required for a design inference.Mung
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
05:51 PM
5
05
51
PM
PDT
Alan, given that philosophy is the love of wisdom, why have you no interest in participating? A "resting skepticism" is isn't very skeptical. Or are you asserting that your skepticism has already provided you with all the knowledge you need, therefore you can rest?Mung
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
05:48 PM
5
05
48
PM
PDT
In re: Torley @ 36, That's a nice point! I don't know my metaphysics of time all that well, but a cursory glance at the relevant Wikipedia articles suggests that I'd endorse the "growing block" version of the A-theory of time. Does that help position me in relation to you and/or Craig?Kantian Naturalist
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
02:55 PM
2
02
55
PM
PDT
@ Vincent I guess you are not now intending to respond to comments on your previous post. Not to worry as the ID movement is gently drifting into cod philosophy and obscurity and I'm giving my scepticism a rest as I think ID is managing to decline very nicely without my input. Best wishes for the future and stay off the whale meat!Alan Fox
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
02:46 PM
2
02
46
PM
PDT
So your quip was lost on me. Perhaps you could explain it in brief terms.Axel
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
09:00 AM
9
09
00
AM
PDT
I'm not a scholar KN, but I've long had the impression that my ignorance of Kant is a big lacuna in my knowledge. However, I have a very narrow focus, now, if potentially fertile in its conspectus.Axel
February 3, 2013
February
02
Feb
3
03
2013
08:59 AM
8
08
59
AM
PDT
Hi Kantian Naturalist, A sudden thought struck me while I was reading your point (4) in comment #18 above. You wrote:
The real problem with final causes is this: once one replaces Aristotle's object-based account with Hume's event-based account, then final causes would seem to require that future events cause present (or past) events; in other words, final causes are incompatible with "time's arrow".
If you're talking about future-directed final causes, then in the absence of a Designer, I agree that they would be incompatible with "time's arrow." What struck me, however, was that you assumed the existence of "time's arrow" in the first place. Many modern-day naturalists deny its existence; in fact, one recent self-styled counter-apologist attacked Dr. William Lane Craig's kalam cosmological argument, in large part because it relies on the A-theory of time, which says that the flow of time is real. The "counter apologist" claims that A-theory runs counter to special relativity, or at least sits very uncomfortably with it. You, on the other hand, defend the A-theory. Here are two scientific papers worth perusing on the subject: The fate of presentism in modern physics by Christian Wuthrich Relativity and the Moving Spotlight by Bradford Skow Thoughts?vjtorley
February 2, 2013
February
02
Feb
2
02
2013
10:32 PM
10
10
32
PM
PDT
Hi Granville Sewell, Thank you for your comment. You write:
"teleological naturalism" seems to be "intelligent design without an intelligent designer." Makes no sense.
I agree. However, I regard it as a big improvement on neo-Darwinian evolutionary naturalism. Unlike the latter, teleological naturalism at least recognizes the inadequacy of non-purposive causal explanations of the cosmos. That's a big step in the right direction, and I respect Thomas Nagel for taking that step.vjtorley
February 2, 2013
February
02
Feb
2
02
2013
09:52 PM
9
09
52
PM
PDT
When ribozymes were first discovered, they were self-transcribing or self-replicating strands of RNA; they could make more copies of themselves. DNA can't do that. To make more copies of a DNA strand, one needs various enzymes to start, guide, and stop the transcription. So you need proteins to make more DNA, and DNA to make proteins. That's the chicken-or-the-egg problem. So it seemed plausible that at first, there was just RNA, chicken and egg in one -- something that can make more copies of itself. (Later on it was discovered that ribozymes are at work in the ribosome.) I haven't been following abiogenesis lately, but my sense is that various objections to the RNA world hypothesis have been piling up, and it's no longer regarded as a plausible scenario. But I don't know that for sure.Kantian Naturalist
February 2, 2013
February
02
Feb
2
02
2013
12:15 PM
12
12
15
PM
PDT
1 2 3

Leave a Reply