Uncommon Descent Serving The Intelligent Design Community

The “is-ought” problem. Is it a true dichotomy or a deceptive bluff?

Share
Facebook
Twitter
LinkedIn
Flipboard
Print
Email

It ain’t what you don’t know that gets you into trouble, it’s what you do know that just ain’t so. — Mark Twain

According to the overrated philosopher, David Hume, we should not try to draw logical conclusions about objective morality based on our knowledge of the real world. This was his smug way of claiming that humans are incapable of knowing the difference between right and wrong.

Through the years, his devoted followers have tweaked his message into a flat out declaration: We cannot derive an “ought to” (a moral code) from the “is.” (the way things are). Just to make sure that we don’t misunderstand, they characterize this formulation as “Hume’s Law.”

The only problem with this philosophy is that it is tragically, clumsily, and inexcusably—wrong. On the contrary, we can learn a great deal about the moral law from the observable facts of nature as long as we acknowledge the point that some truths are self-evident.

Unfortunately, hyper-skeptics cannot grasp this point because they first fail to understand that morality is a measure of, and is dependent on, what is good. If there is no (objective) good, then morality cannot exist. But we know that some things, such as life, are obviously good for humans – universally, absolutely, and objectively good. It is the same for goods that flow from life, such as the desire to survive and reproduce. As would be expected of objectively good things, they exist in a hierarchy, which means that we can differentiate between lower goods (wants) and higher goods (needs).

People want food that is pleasing to the palate, for example, but they need food that meets their nutritional requirements. The latter good is more important than the former, even if it is not perceived to be so. If one allows his desire for pleasure to overpower his desire for good health, he will eventually lose the capacity to be pleased and the opportunity to be healthy. It is self-evident to any rational person that the desire for long-term health is a higher good than the desire for momentary pleasure.

So it is with sex. Humans may want to experience immediate physical gratification, but if they ignore the higher needs, such as the desire for love and respect, they will harm themselves and others. Sexual responsibility is less about submitting to the technology of birth control and more about responding to the challenge of self-disciplined behavior.

Again, through nature, we learn that the good of procreation is made possible by the complementarity of the species. That is why a marriage is properly defined as the union of one man and one woman: the difference between them allows them to unite in one flesh. Two members of the same sex cannot become one flesh because it is the complementarity that makes the oneness possible. From Biology, we also discover that sex has a specific function, which means that it can be misused by those who do not respect its intended purpose.

From the all this information about the “is,” (complementarity and biology) we can derive four distinct moral conclusions: [a] Men should not have sex with men. [b] Women should not have sex with women. [c] Same sex marriage cannot and does not exist. [d] Any law that defines so-called “gay marriage” as a true marriage is an evil lie and should be resisted.

In a broader sense, the lower goods, such as fun, pleasure, and delight, are designed as an incentive for pursuing the higher goods, such as love, self-esteem, self-control, meaning, and purpose, which are the ones that matter most in any discussion of morality. Because we really need them, they are good for us and we ought to have them. As Mortimer Adler says, we ought to desire whatever is really good for us and nothing else.

From the testimony of social scientists, we learn that humans are social beings, so we may safely conclude that they ought to reproduce, build families and establish communities. In every area of life, there are legitimate moral needs that ought to be pursued and illegitimate wants that ought to be eschewed.

Moral growth, therefore, involves a definitive behavioral strategy: We should learn to like what is good for us and to dislike what is bad for us. In other words, we should form good habits so that they will crowd out the bad habits. Nature not only teaches us about the need for virtue, it also helps us to acquire it through practice. Psychologists tell us that it takes three to six weeks to form a new habit.

The take home message, then, should be clear: Beware of the hyper-skeptical doctrine that goes by the name of Hume’s “law.” The so-called “is – ought” dichotomy is a deceptive bluff. It poses no intellectual challenge to the natural moral law or the human capacity to apprehend it.

 

 

Comments
Barry
When I use is/ought, I mean that IF metaphysical materialism is a true account of reality, then there can be no morality whatsoever. Particles in motion are amoral. Therefore, if all of reality consists of nothing but particles in motion, all of reality is amoral
Right. If materialism is true (the secular “is”) then there can be no morality. I think kf uses it the same way. Indeed, so do I. It is a perfectly legitimate way to argue.
Of course, that is a big IF. It is self-evident that we are morally governed. That is one of many reasons to reject metaphysical materialism.
Right again. Of course, my aim is to show that we can know we are morally governed by pointing to higher and lower levels on the moral scale.
Thus, I use the formulation in two ways: (1) to show that materialists are on a fool’s errand if they believe they can ground a morality that amounts to more than “I prefer” in their premises; and (2) to show that their premises must be false, because they lead to absurd conclusions.
Yes, again, this is a good way to go, and it obviously works. You let them assume that the prescriptive cannot be connected to the descriptive and defeat them on that basis. Of course, I am trying to show that that the descriptive can be connected with the prescriptive and that the universe screams moral design. I don’t think there is any conflict between our views – only our methods.StephenB
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
04:32 PM
4
04
32
PM
PDT
I see that Allan and Bob have weighed in. They have been trying for years to demonstrate that their materialist morality is grounded in something more firm than glandular impulses. So far they have failed. Let's see what they come up with this time.Barry Arrington
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
03:03 PM
3
03
03
PM
PDT
SB, When I use is/ought, I mean that IF metaphysical materialism is a true account of reality, then there can be no morality whatsoever. Particles in motion are amoral. Therefore, if all of reality consists of nothing but particles in motion, all of reality is amoral. Of course, that is a big IF. It is self-evident that we are morally governed. That is one of many reasons to reject metaphysical materialism. Thus, I use the formulation in two ways: (1) to show that materialists are on a fool's errand if they believe they can ground a morality that amounts to more than "I prefer" in their premises; and (2) to show that their premises must be false, because they lead to absurd conclusions.Barry Arrington
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
03:00 PM
3
03
00
PM
PDT
On the contrary, we can learn a great deal about the moral law from the observable facts of nature as long as we acknowledge the point that some truths are self-evident.
Yes, there are self evident truths. If I die before puberty I will not have children is a self evident truth. But the fact that there are self evident truths does not translate into “morality must be objective”.Allan Keith
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
03:00 PM
3
03
00
PM
PDT
johnnyb
What I mean is that if, by “is”, you mean the precise physical makeup of nature – matter, possitions, velocities, then it is 100% true. You cannot derive an ought based solely on a physicochemical makeup of matter.
Yes, there is a narrow bands of "is(s)" from which we cannot derive a moral conclusion. Another example would be this: We cannot derive an ought to from the is by simply observing the way humans behave. I would add, though, that we can derive an ought to based on the purposeful arrangement of matter. Hence, the example of the complementarity of the sexes.
However, if you allow “is” to include other types of things – spiritual things – then you can derive oughts from is’s, not in the least because some oughts *are* is’s. That is, if the moral structure of the world is an “is”, then you can derive oughts from is’s.
Advocates for the is/ought "problem" use the word "is" without qualification. That is the whole point - to say that we cannot apprehend the natural moral law regardless of which "is" we may turn to. Otherwise, there would be no point it characterizing it as a law and an argument against natural law or our capacity to apprehend it. You will notice that they never said that we can know morality in this way but not in that way. Their claim is that we cannot know it at all. If they can open it up to all the "is(s", then so can I. Indeed, I submit that we do, indeed, live in a moral universe.StephenB
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
02:07 PM
2
02
07
PM
PDT
SB: But we know that some things, such as life, are obviously good for humans – universally, absolutely, and objectively good. It is the same for goods that flow from life, such as the desire to survive and reproduce. Bob
From which one can conclude that rape is good if it leads to a child (and the mother who was raped doesn’t die, of course).
Bad logic, Life is good for a fetus. Life is also good for a mother. That doesn't mean that rape, a bad act, is a good act if it happens to produce a positive effect along with all the obvious bad effects. Bad acts can produce some positive consequences, just as good acts can produce some negative consequences.
Yes, morality can difficult.
That is why I am here to help.StephenB
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
01:34 PM
1
01
34
PM
PDT
I think the "is-ought" is useful for talking about a *particular* type of "is". It also shows why other types of is's are important. What I mean is that if, by "is", you mean the precise physical makeup of nature - matter, possitions, velocities, then it is 100% true. You cannot derive an ought based solely on a physicochemical makeup of matter. Now, if position, velocity, etc. were the only is's available, then that would mean that there were no oughts at all, or at least none that we could detect. Therefore, morality would be fruitless. However, if you allow "is" to include other types of things - spiritual things - then you can derive oughts from is's, not in the least because some oughts *are* is's. That is, if the moral structure of the world is an "is", then you can derive oughts from is's.johnnyb
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
01:30 PM
1
01
30
PM
PDT
But we know that some things, such as life, are obviously good for humans – universally, absolutely, and objectively good. It is the same for goods that flow from life, such as the desire to survive and reproduce.
From which one can conclude that rape is good if it leads to a child (and the mother who was raped doesn't die, of course). Yes, morality can difficult.Bob O'H
June 18, 2018
June
06
Jun
18
18
2018
01:07 PM
1
01
07
PM
PDT
1 3 4 5

Leave a Reply